 ORIGINAL ARTICLE

The essences of and corporal fighting: A classical phenomenological analysis Authors’ Contribution: A Study Design B Data Collection Cristiano Roque Antunes Barreira C Statistical Analysis D Manuscript Preparation School of Physical Education and Sport of Ribeirão Preto, University of São Paulo, São Paulo, Brazil E Funds Collection Received: 17 May 2016; Accepted: 11 September 2017; Published online: 22 November 2017

AoBID: 11807

Abstract

Literature does not provide a clear conceptualisation of the fighting at the core of martial arts. In fact, there is not even a precise definition of martial arts. It is common to find descriptions of martial arts fighting as a derivation, simulacra, or metaphorical phenomenon of human conflict, i.e. a phenomenon without its proper dignity. To discover its proper dignity is the main goal of this theoretical research. Achieving this goal can be of fundamental importance to the whole of the research field and to clarify norms of practice regarding the two phenomena (fighting and martial arts). Methodologically, classical phenomenology, or the archaeological phenomenology of culture, is applied to grasp the essence of these phenomena, in order to return to the things themselves. Moreover, the phenome- nal distinction of corporal fighting leads to a correlative ethical aspect, namely, the mutual availability of the fighters involved and the motivation inherent in the challenge of physically overcoming another while avoid- ing being overcome. All varieties of martial arts involve a form of corporal fight training that unites aesthetical and ethical aspects. In the systematisation of corporal fighting, the aesthetical dimension defines one aspect of martial arts, including its operative nature; the other aspect is defined by an enhanced typification of the ethical dimension comprised therein. In other words, the ethical dimension is characterised by conduct that typically relates to combative attitudes. Lived experiences constituting fighting and martial arts have scien- tific and ethical consequences.

Keywords: archaeological phenomenology • budo • sports • self-defence • simulacra • sport psychology Copyright: © 2017 the Author. Published by Archives of Budo Conflict of interest: Author has declared that no competing interest exists Ethical approval: Not required Provenance & peer review: Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed

Source of support: This work was supported by the FAPESP, grant number 2012/22729-0 Author’s address: Cristiano Roque Antunes Barreira, Escola de Educação Física e Esporte de Ribeirão Preto, Universidade de São Paulo, Av. Bandeirantes, 3900 - Monte Alegre, Ribeirão Preto, Brazil; e-mail: [email protected]

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 351

This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0), which permits use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited, the use is non-commercial and is otherwise in compliance with the license. Original Article

INTRODUCTION Agonology (science about for comparison in the literature regarding specific struggle) – five detailed theories of agonology were This philosophical and psychological theoreti- practices found in the unique facets of martial published in 6 separate books cal investigation aims to define the essence of arts, combat sports, and fighting. This happens (from 1938 to 2000, all in Polish [83-88]). two phenomena: martial arts (budo) and what even when different researchers face sharing the I call corporal fighting. The methodological per- same theme as those aiming to analyse the socio- Struggle – any activity that spective adopted in this study represents classi- psychological outcomes of martial arts and com- is at least a two-subject one (premising that a team can be cal phenomenology, which attempts to grasp the bat sports involvement, specifical issues such as a subject) where at least one essence of the objects it studies, in order to back aggression and [4]. Theeboom [5] tried of subjects hinders the other [83; see also: 73, 74, 93, 94]. to the things themselves. The primary phenome- to ‘help to explain why a number of studies have nal feature of corporal fighting, that is, its defining resulted in contrasting findings’ [5, p.200], argu- Fight– in the popular Diki characteristic on the face of things is a physi- ing that ‘only through a more nuanced way of Dictionary, there are 19 basic synonyms of the term (nouns); cal confrontation; however, this characteristic is analysis might we be able to dissolve the exist- 14 verbs; 2 phrasal verbs; 2 common to other phenomena as well. Moreover, ing paradox and can we start to detect the true idioms. as will be reviewed and analytically shown, the effects of martial arts involvement among youth’ Budo (Budō) – originally a phenomenical non-distinction between corpo- [5, p.201]. Before detecting these effects, we term denoting the “Way of the warrior”, it is now used ral fightingand fighting in a broad sense (as does argue here; it is imperative to know what these as a collective appellation agonology, i.e. science about struggle, however, phenomena, fighting and martial arts, truly are, for modern martial arts of kendō, jūdō, kyūdo and so due to the author limitation in reading Polish, it through an even more nuanced (though more rig- on. The primary objective of was not possible to examine the literature on orous) way of analysis. these “martial ways” is self- perfection (ningen- kesei) [89]. agonology. The Editors warn that it is a science about struggles, which allows establishing that The present research is conceptual and car- – a Brazilian kind of distinction. For a better comprehension, ries out a philosophical exploration that aims to martial art in which “fighting overcomes the fight itself, see the glossary added by the Editors, as well as define the essence of both fighting and martial encompassing the practice of the Editorial Note) leads to a serious misunder- arts. A phenomenological analysis is done, whose a ritualistic game since dance comes up from musicality and standing about their natures, with scientific, eth- results provide criteria - inherent to the subject/ rhythm; attacks and defenses ical, and motivational confusion about the true object, a feature that phenomenology aims to occur within a people wheel (roda), formed by the and cultural meanings of martial arts. make explicit- that make possible to conceptu- practitioner (capoeiristas) and alize fighting and martial arts, defining them at the public” [36, p. 178]. The scientific community’s burgeoning interest the light of their various forms of empirical man- (KM) – Israelian in issues inherent to martial arts, fighting, and ifestation and distinguishing them from similar self-defence system, combat sports, such as Japanese -do, Israeli phenomena. The research aims to contribute to developed from military experience and constantly krav maga, Olympic , and tae-kwondo, is the whole of the research field and clarify norms updated by violent incidents in evidenced by the ever-growing number of pub- of practice regarding the two phenomena. The the military, law enforcement and civil arenas, taught to lications ‒ which will be presented below ‒ and definitions provided by the Anglo-Saxon and security forces and civilians the growing scientific impact of Archives of Budo Latin literature regarding these cultural objects worldwide. [1]. Although interest in martial arts and com- are not founded on phenomenological analysis. Global science space – bat sports (MA&CS) is still dispersed among Moreover, the consulted bibliography in English, conventionally, the global science space is associated scientific publications [2] that pertain to differ- Spanish, French, Italian, and Portuguese do not with the ability to provide the ent study areas or among national and interna- offer a precise definition that encompasses latest scientific knowledge through prestigious electronic tional scientific events, it does extend beyond the wide variety of practices found in these scientific journals [75]. the fields of physical education and sports. In phenomena. this sense, continuous contributions from other Simulacra – are copies that depict things that either had no areas, such as psychology, sociology, and philos- Even if there is no novelty in applying phenom- original, to begin with or that ophy, address these issues, thereby enriching the enology to sports psychology, or still to physi- no longer have an original [91]. scope of possible interpretations of martial arts cal education [6-16], the purpose of grasping the SWAT – Special Weapons And and combat sports. However, this growing inter- intentional structure of lived experiences is still Tactics. est is not associated with any sort of conceptual incipient not only in sports psychology but also clarity via any linking element that would provide in psychology as a whole. In adherence to the thematic unity among these fields of study. As Husserlian method, we took an original approach argued by Martinkóvá and Parry [3], ‘In both the- in applying classical phenomenology to the anal- ory and practice, there is presently terminological ysis of cultural phenomena [17, 18]. chaos in the area of martial activities’ [3, p.3]. The absence of a common thematic and terminolog- In phenomenology, the use of precise words is ical unit poses problems for the scientific com- important for avoiding ambiguity; it is particu- munity, in that it makes it difficult to find grounds larly important to describe phenomena clearly.

352 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

Words and expressions used generically are often to the theme at hand. As already mentioned, unsuitable. As Husserl states, ‘phenomenology ‘describing and precisely defining the martial arts is never content, on principle, with vague talk or has provided an ongoing challenge for authors obscure generalities, but systematically demands and theorists’ [20, p. 9]. Some studies from dif- a definite clarification, analysis and descrip- ferent regions ‒ including America, Europe, Asia, tion shedding light on the essential connexions and Oceania ‒ illustrate this fact. In their other- and penetrating to the remotest specifications wise exhaustive encyclopaedia of Eastern mar- attainable: it demands thoroughgoing work’ [19, tial arts, Habersetzer G and Habersetzer R [21] p. 417]. Once a phenomenon is described, the do not dedicate a single chapter to defining their word or term used to describe it is conceptual- subject matter. Even Keenan [22] ‒ mirroring ised; the current use of the word does not nec- the approach adopted in almost every bibliog- essarily change, but its philosophical significance raphy ‒ does not offer any definition of ‘mar- becomes more precise. To obtain a better under- tial arts’; like the authors previously mentioned, standing of the phenomena focused on in this he merely speaks of ‘Eastern martial arts’. Thus, study, it is appropriate to coin a new expression: these authors seem, implicitly, to share the popu- corporal fighting. The term ‘fighting’ is generally lar approach of narrowly interpreting martial arts taken to refer to various forms of ‘physical com- in terms of the word budo, the Japanese term bat’, whereas corporal fighting refers only to that for martial arts (loosely meaning ‘warrior path’). kind of fighting in which the body plays a central The relation between the definitions of martial role as a tool, target, and motivator. arts and budo is pointed out by Braunstein [23] and by Kalina and Barczyński [24, 2]). In a broad Physical combat includes the use of weapons in sense, as adopted here, budo is synonymous with fighting but also encompasses struggles (here martial arts, the usual translation of the expres- used as street fighting or brawls), battles, duels, sion. Although, it is interesting that Sasaki warns, self-defence, and some forms of play, all of which ‘Historically, the term Budo has had a very broad ‒ as will be shown ‒ are excluded from the scope meaning’ [25, p. 47], even in Japan, and that of corporal fighting if the body is not the central ‘although the concept of Budo has been argued tool, target, and motivator. Moreover, the idea of about from many points of view, it has not yet physical combat is not restricted to the notion of been clearly defined’ [25]. physical struggle (brawl), nor vice versa, if physi- cal combat is taken to include cases of play, duel- A likely problem with this approach is that it ling, self-defence, or corporal fighting, all of which may associate the concept with very specific are irreducible to the idea of ‘struggle’. When ref- cultural terms and with theoretical and practi- erencing acts of self-defence, struggling, or duel- cal references that, in the context, lead ling, the word ‘fighting’ tends to bear meanings in to an erroneous inference that the only authen- addition to the typical meanings, such meanings tic martial arts are those originating in the East. being determined by the motivations inherent in According to this interpretation, Western martial the act of fighting. Once the expression coined arts would amount to nothing more than cop- in this article is clarified and disseminated, there ied versions of models originating in the East, will be a wider and more comprehensive grasp which is not accurate if one takes into account of the essence of martial arts. This need for the the martial art forms prevalent in Europe ‒ medi- coining of a new concept has been brought about eval and martial arts [26], the martial by the lack of conceptual accuracy in the Anglo- arts of Ancient Greece [27] that is, the so-called Saxon and Latin literature, which has led to a fail- European historical martial arts [28] ‒ or capoe- ure to individuate such phenomena and explain ira, a martial art form developed in Brazil [29], for their specificities. instance. There is an evident paradox in the asso- ciation of martial arts with the East: its etymol- Achieving goal of this work can be of fundamen- ogy is entirely occidental, referring to Mars, the tal importance to the whole of the research field ancient Roman god of war. Even if we do not talk and to clarify norms of practice regarding the two about ‘areal arts’, i.e. the arts of Ares, the ancient phenomena (fighting and martial arts). Greek god of war who was considered disrup- tive and impulsive, and who did not have the vir- Literature review tuous character of Mars, it is possible to find the A cursory literature review reveals a lack of con- employment of an alternative expression which ceptual unity among the various approaches avoids (and opposes) the suggestion of a specific

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 353 Original Article

military practice in martial arts: ‘civil fighting tra- this exclusion, in association with his arguments ditions’ [30, p. 23]. deployed, results in an understanding of martial arts in the context of a Western philosophical This alternative expression, though interesting idea of self-overcoming. Monahan’s definition is to an eventual kind of classification of combat promising and full of well-founded moral conse- techniques, apparently is not explicitly justified quences, but it clearly restricts martial arts to this and seems to be particular to McCarthy’s text. philosophical idea. Beyond this, it can promote confusion, since civil fighting can be rigorously understood as political Although the objective of Columbus and Rice fighting, or fighting for civil rights, in which phys- [38] is not to define martial arts but to compre- ical combat ideally is not expected to occur. On hend phenomenologically the various meanings the other hand, Eastern versus Western styles, imparted to these arts by its practitioners, the i.e. a classification based on cultural differences authors mention that aspects related to emanci- ‒ or, more precisely, geographical differences, we pation, religion, and military practices are part of should say ‒ is arguably the most popular way to its historical definition, while placing emphasis on classify martial arts [31]. Theeboom et al. [32] psychological maturation and skills acquisition. merely classify combat systems as ‘indigenous Vey [20] refutes the dimension of meanings that fighting sports (e.g. boxing, , and fenc- martial arts could have and, regarding its defini- ing) that have been practiced in Europe for a long tion, suggests that ‘the elusiveness of this task time, other systems (e.g. , jiu-jitsu, and karate) seems to rest in the inherently dichotomous per- found their way from Far-East Asia to the West in ception of the martial arts in that they are simul- later times’, and, suggesting an Eurocentric stand- taneously regarded as a physical phenomenon point, state that after ‘the spread of Asian martial of combat and a metaphysical set of beliefs and arts to the West (…) gradually, fighting systems ideologies’ [20, p. 8]. That is, in fact, the case in from other parts of the world, too, found their Cynarski’s [39] definition, where martial arts are way to the West (e.g. Brazilian Capoeira)’ [32, p. understood as ‘a historical category of perfect 19]. The authors argue that the variety of com- systems of the hand-to-hand fight and wielding bat systems ‘over recent decades has made it less weapon connected with elements of metaphys- than straightforward to refer to martial arts as a ics’ [39, p. 20). Therefore, adhering to dualism and unitary phenomenon’ [32, p. 19]. However, they a radically positivistic perspective, Vey under- do not define martial arts; they only suggest ways stands that ‘an operational definition of what to classify it. They consider a convention followed constitutes the phenomenon is also required. In by Kavoura et al. [33] that uses ‘the terms combat this case, combat is the physical instance of a sports and martial arts interchangeably to refer deliberate and volitional motor series produced to all combat systems’ [33, p. 2]. exclusively by humans’ [20, p. 11]. The extreme weakness of his attempt to define martial arts is Moreover, without intending to define ‘mar- patent since it contains not only the combative tial arts’, Looser’s [34] sociological analysis and phenomena but also any other corporal move- Lantz’s [35] therapeutic analysis study athletes in ment intentionally made by a human being. New Zealand and the United States, respectively, practising martial arts originating in the East; Then, it is not possible to disagree with Correia these studies reinforce the message that there and Franchini [40], who say that ‘the disagree- are cultural particularities in martial arts originat- ment demarcates and characterises the dialogue ing in the East. This perception is also suggested among the different actors making the historical by Lu [36], who clarifies, ‘Not to be confused with scene that represents the field of fighting, mar- what in the West may be perceived as «physical» tial arts, and combat sports’ [40, p. 1]. Taking a activities, Eastern martial arts are instead consid- broad approach to the notion of fighting, with ered to be «philosophical» activities’ [36, p.33]. emphasis on the anthropological dimension, Elsewhere, Monahan’s [37] philosophical reading which is excluded from the positivistic approach, deliberately limits the definition of ‘martial arts’ the authors argue towards a polysemous view to traditional practices in which the emphasis is and conclude that, in ‘lato sensu, we have the sit- less on the instrumental accuracy of combat than uations in which that term [fighting] is circum- on artistic facets. Monahan’s definition excludes scribed in the context of physical/bodily combat instrumental combat practices, such as those per- by intent of subjugations between subjects start- formed in military and competitive contexts, and ing with interpersonal conflicts and, always, by

354 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

contradictory and ambivalent human content’ Therefore, Poliakoff [42] escapes from the his- [40, p. 1]. However, how do we understand this toricism of Reid and Croucher [42]1, from the view that not all fighting happens because of an positivistic naturalism of Vey [20], and from the interpersonal conflict? The authors would answer psychologistic fault of Correia and Franchini [40], that we do so by seeing it as a ‘war metaphor’. who consider who consider fighting always as This line of interpretation is indeed assumed by metaphorical expression of interpersonal con- many other authors. flicts. However, the question that remains is: how are all of those combat categories constituted? Conceptually – compared to previous research on this topic – Figueiredo [41] made landmark In a version similar to the pair ‘fight’ and ‘ritu- progress with his research. In his approach to alistic fight, Sanchez García and Malcolm [44], the study of martial arts and combat sports, based on Norbert Elias and Eric Dunning, inter- Figueiredo highlighted a hermeneutical pret the modern sportive phenomenon as a approach as suitable for considering the sub- search for ‘mimetic’ excitement. Parallel to the ject, because it allows for a proper cognisance concepts of ‘real life’ excitement and ‘mimetic’ of the complexity involved. In his conceptuali- excitement, the concepts of ‘real life combat’ sation of the subject, Figueiredo [41, p. 20] dis- and ‘mock fights’ were introduced. The former tinguished between the ‘fight’ (in which the ‘kill ‘is reserved for unregulated combat such as street is real’) and the ‘ritualistic fight’ (in which the fighting’ [44, p. 42]. Yet, the authors state that ‘kill is more symbolic’); the latter, because of its ‘participants in combat sports explicitly recog- sublime aspect, allows martial arts and combat nise the differences between the “mock fights”, sports to be defined as disciplines, rather than for which they train, and “real fighting”’ [44, p. as real fights. Nevertheless, the intentional spec- 42]. Although they highlight that ‘mock fights’ ificity of these phenomena in not examined in are used ‘to recognise qualitative differences, terms of their essence, that is to say, in ontolog- and that combat sports people identify between ical terms, but only in terms of the hermeneutic these activities rather than portray the fighting perspective applied by Figueiredo in his import- in combat sports as “unreal”’ [44, p. 42], they ant contribution. Figueiredo follows some ideas do not offer a conceptual definition of fighting. of Reid and Croucher [42]. Although they asked Therefore, fighting and martial arts are under- ‘what exactly do we mean by ‘martial arts’ [42, stood as a kind of cathartic representation of p. 10], the answer is not exact, as it is limited real fighting, of real conflict. Although represen- to a significant overview of historical aspects tation is important, only an accurate description that were determinants in its probable devel- can express the essence of these phenomena, not opment: ‘The fundamental division into fight- as a representation of anything else, but as phe- ing as entertainment, sport or ritual, performed nomena having their own dignity. within the tribe, and warfare, which is combat against other tribes, probably occurred in pre- Recently, Martínková and Parry [3] emphasised historic times. By the time the first civilisations the prominent conceptual differences and con- were well established this division had become fusion in the field, and stated, ‘there is no satis- ritualised’ [42, p. 12]. In another work often ref- factory and well justified cross-cultural account erenced, Poliakoff [43] took an approach that of the classification of martial activities’ [3, p. 4). encompasses important distinctions and defi- They comment that, in ‘the fine collection edited nitions whose contents may be understood as by Priest and Young (2014)’ [3, p. 2], among chap- contractualistic: I define Sport and athletics (...) ters of a dozen philosophers, ‘their conceptions of as activity in which a person physically competes “martial arts” vary considerably’ [3, p. 2]. Echoing against another in a contest with established regu- the editors, for whom a ‘question about the mar- lations and procedures, with the immediate object tial arts is how to characterise them’ [45, p. 9], of succeeding in that contest under criteria for they ‘address this hard, non-trivial philosophical determining victory that are different from those question’ [3, p. 2] and ‘propose a classification that mark success in everyday life. (...) This defini- of martial activities based on the purpose of the tion of sport excludes a number of forms of combat, activity’ [3, p. 2]. The clear eidetic classification of such as , armed duelling, and gladiatorial events, activities that fall more properly into cate- 1. The historicist approach taken by the authors, who con- gories other than sport [42, p. 7]. sider a common development from prehistoric times, suggests an evolutionistic conception. Therefore, it may be as well interpreted as naturalistic.

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 355 Original Article

the purpose of what they call martial categories, that were not evident but were sensed obscurely. and its usefulness, however, is not the same of The methodological approach adopted in this back to physical combat and martial arts as things paper has been sourced from classical phenom- themselves but is centred around what is possi- enology, which uses eidetic and transcendental ble to do (and what is made) considering the exis- reduction as a way to isolate the essential features tence of these phenomena. Once again, we can of a phenomenon, made by a thing consistent with detect the dichotomous pair of ‘real-life fighting its intentional comade consistently with its inten- with the aim of defending oneself or defeating tional consciousness.omenology ‘proceeds with an opponent’ [3, p. 8] and ‘combat in a modi- an excavation sui generis that moves not from the fied form, given the lack of any real need to fight surface, but from interiority’ [51, p. 5]. She goes someone’ [3, p. 9]. For someone, knowing fight- on to say that the transcendental dimension is the ing, the things learned by practising a martial art, dimension of the acts, the operations of which we provides the better condition to act in both the are conscious, which we ‘live’ at every moment of real combat and the supposed non-real com- our existence, these are the acts that are lived by bat (modified, metaphorical, symbolised). What us, our ‘lived experience’, or Erlebnisse (in German). exactly does the lack of any real need to fight The acts we live are consciously grasped by us, mean, considering that when someone is prac- which means that we are aware that we are liv- tising combat in martial arts, he feels in his flesh ing them [51, p. 5]. the need to fight to defend himself and defeat his opponent? Therefore, the definition of fight- Therefore, we can recognise and then analyse ing and martial arts are still unclear from a phe- those specificities among the synthesis of lived nomenological point of view. experiences present in the flow of conscious- ness. In this operation, the object is approached In the pedagogical field of physical education and with a readjusted attitude; the accepted assump- sports, a very fruitful line of research has been tions with regard to the object are suspended devoted to examining the internal logic of fight- in order to extract only what is manifest. This ing practices [41, 46-50]. Different ways to clas- approach does not view the objects as ‘beings in sify and characterise the phenomenon of fighting themselves’ but as ‘beings for a subject’, reveal- are presented in these works, most of them aim- ing themselves as things to the conscious, which ing to explain the principles that organise the is always conscious of something. Here, we fol- functions of the combative exchange. However, low what Husserl [19] defined as ‘the principle of what is the fighting phenomenon itself remains all principles’: ‘Every primordial dator Intuition is a to be elucidated. The absence of clear answers source of authority for knowledge, that whatever in the literature to questions about combat cat- presents itself in intuition in primordial form (as it egories (see Editorial Note – insertion by Arch were in its bodily reality), is simply to be accepted as Budo), i.e. of what fighting and martial arts con- it gives itself out to be, though only within the limits sist, inspires the analyses done herein. The search in which it presents itself’. [19, p. 92]. for a definition can be undertaken with the inten- tion of highlighting non-definitions or vague defi- The reduction is dealt with as a procedure that nitions of ‘martial arts’ in the groundwork on aims to subtract those characteristics of a phe- which these research works are based. nomenon that are shown to be mere accessories, thus limiting itself to the phenomenological ori- Methodology entation and essence of a phenomenon. To verify Phenomenology was founded in the early twen- the essential stability of a phenomenon (without tieth century by the philosopher Edmund Husserl which that phenomenon is not as it previously (1859–1938). Its major objective was to develop was), the criteria used are of the eidetic variety a gnosiology able to pinpoint the ultimate rational ‒ or those in which different outcomes of a phe- inherent in scientific practices. Phenomenology nomenon are considered ‒ so as to guarantee the would thus serve as a propaedeutic for the sci- persistence of its structure. This persistence cor- ences. With regard to the sciences and the human responds to the essential stability of the phenom- condition, phenomenological research reveals enon. By performing this operation, it is possible implicit elements and ideal possibilities that shape to derive an internal description of those lived both scientific practice and the perception of exis- experiences which characterise the phenome- tence. The task of phenomenology was to make non or, in this case, phenomena, namely, corpo- explicit the implicit elements, that is, the elements ral fightingand martial arts.

356 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

For a reader not familiar with phenomenology, a martial art form that does not involve corporal the progress of such analyses may eventually fighting, even though it is reasonable to concep- seem to follow simple logical syllogisms and not tualise the converse. what is called here eidetic reduction. In fact, the problems of logic, and the imperative need of Imagining is an act of consciousness central to logic are decisive, corresponding to a historical the procedure of eidetic variation described starting point for the phenomenology of Husserl, by Husserl [19]. The eidetic variation, or act of who was a mathematician. Without escaping imagining, is accomplished by the insertion and logic, the fundamental distinction is that, here, removal of features that are potentially essential logic complies with the intuition of the phenom- to the phenomenon being examined for arriving enon, is oriented entirely by it. Therefore, it does at a lowest common denominator, i.e. the phe- not concern the correction between sentences, nomenon’s essence. Thus, in considering the idea as the syllogism. Indeed, it concerns sentences of ‘martial arts’, if one imagines subtracting the that must be veridical in terms of adhering to presence of corporal fightingfrom martial arts, an things, i.e. expresses adequately the return to the essential impossibility will be faced. There is no things themselves, as Husserl stated: ‘Perfectly martial art without corporal fighting, whether real clear apprehension has this advantage, that in vir- or imaginary. The opposite, however, is not true, tue of its own essential nature it permits us with i.e. if the idea of ‘martial arts’ ‒ even if it is still absolute certainty to identify and distinguish, to an obscure idea ‒ is subtracted from the idea of relate and make explicit, enable us, briefly, to corporal fighting, the essence of the latter idea carry out “with insight” and “logical” acts’ [19 p. remains intact. Without the idea of ‘martial arts’, 197]. This means overcoming the uniqueness of a the essence of corporal fighting is retained and case, of an individual example: ‘It is only the indi- can have real or ideal forms independent of the vidual element which phenomenology ignores, notion of ‘martial arts’. This is the case for some whilst it raises the whole essential content in its forms of combat sports, such as box and wres- concrete fullness into eidetic consciousness and tling, which are not necessarily relative to cul- takes it as an ideally selfsame essence, which like tural notions of martial arts. Further clarification every essence could particularize itself not only of this, however, depends on a precise phenom- hic et nunc but in numberless instances’ [19 p. enological analysis of martial arts phenomena. 209]. Phenomenology, therefore, precedes the Once the more general nature of corporal fight- sciences of facts that ‘must find support in such ing is clarified in relation to martial arts, the rea- acts, it makes nonetheless, as a fundamental con- son for focusing on corporal fighting as an object dition of its possibility, positive affirmations con- will be easier to grasp. cerning unreflective experiences. These it owes to reflexion, or, more accurately, to the reflective It is necessary to clarify here that corporal fight- intuition of the essence’ [19, p. 225]. According ing does not refer to any form of institutionalised to the issues discussed in this paper, what we do physical confrontation regulated by external rules is ‘psychology in the sense of a doctrine of psy- that control the conduct of the participants and chic or spiritual essences that studies the psy- which involves the criteria of victory and defeat. che empirically and a priori in its own particular This description is more suitable ‒ although phe- essence according to its immanent set of types nomenologically imprecise ‒ as a definition of [Typik]’ [52, p. 8]. ‘’ than of corporal fighting. The term corporal fighting is a new concept that refers to a phenomenon that encompasses all combat sports types, although this premise is not entirely WHAT IS CORPORAL FIGHTING? accurate. It must be noted here that, conceptually, corpo- ral fighting embodies a concept of a more general This analysis has already suspended the informa- nature when compared to the concept of ‘mar- tive institutional definition ‒or so-called natural tial arts’; it loosely encapsulates the field of mar- definition ‒ that seeks to identify or apprehend tial arts, while it is possible to include corporal what is immediate in corporal fighting. What, fightingunder the rubric of martial arts. Thus, the then, is exhibited in corporal fighting? As already various martial arts embody specific ways of cor- mentioned, the primary phenomenal feature of poral fighting. The truth of this statement is evi- corporal fighting lies in physical confrontation; dent in the fact that it is impossible to imagine however, other phenomena ‒such as physical

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 357 Original Article

struggles, duels, instrumental offensive combat, developed later. From the image of the fighters self-defence, and some forms of play ‒ share the greeting and combating each other, mentioned same characteristics and thus lie on the fringes of above, we pass now to the moment when one of the experience of corporal fighting, extending the the practitioners, finding himself dominated and analysis even further. Mere similarities are not even disappointed, accepts his defeat and stops synonymous with being identical, and although the fighting. these phenomena could be mistaken for each other, their characteristics reveal differences In a physical struggle (street fighting), confron- between them. We should caution here that the tation is invariably motivated by hostility. This next analytical steps will make the reductions in motivation reifies the other entity as something order to get the pure manifestations of phenom- disaffected. As the target of hostility, the other ena, identifying the acts of pure consciousness entity is not recognised as having positive moti- of which phenomena originally consisted. These vations, and so the agent is closed to the other. In phenomena can occur impurely, that is, with the this closed condition, the agent always perceives right mix of acts. These occurrences are not only the other as a negative and threatening entity. a fact, but also the source of imprecise concepts This hostility characterises the inherent unilateral on the subject. nature of the physical struggle, in stark contrast to the mutuality of corporal fighting. The idea of inherent motivation and ethical correlatives with regard to physical struggles An intemperate emotional outbreak occurs only in appears again Husserl’s statement: ‘the vast on occasion during conflict and is therefore not manifold of meaning-objectivities, that is to say, an essential feature of physical struggle, which is levels of meaning in physical things and subjec- conceived as the simple possibility of somebody tivities, are understandable [verstehbare] objec- struggling ‘coldly’, without showing emotional tivities, and their scientific exploration is nothing engagement of any kind even if the struggle is else than just engendering understanding, clarify- accompanied by the necessary hostility, closure, ing motivations’ [52, p. 9]. The first fundamental and unilaterality of regarding the other as an distinction that surfaces in corporal fightingis the attack target. Hence, the physical struggle does mutual availability of the participants: both are not embrace the ethical reciprocity inherent in willing to fight, and both are aware of each oth- corporal fighting, namely, the mutual availability er’s willingness to fight. This is well exemplified and inherent motivation. in the simple image of two practitioners of any kind of fighting greeting each other and engaging In a duel, the motivation for confrontation is the peacefully ‒ even if done with much energy ‒ in protection of one’s . How do we know combat, with one trying to dominate the other. this? Again, by the imaginative variation that opens the way for the eidetic reduction in the The second fundamental characteristic is that cor- purpose of reaching an element that is impos- poral fighting finds motivation in itself ‒ namely, sible to subtract from the phenomenon with- in the challenge of overcoming the opponent out disfiguring it, an element that is therefore while avoiding being overcome. The phenome- essential to the phenomenon. If one were to set nal apprehension of corporal fightingthus implies aside the honour component—that is, wounded the possibility of recognition that both opponents self-respect demanding reprisal—the duel would participating in combat are deliberately available cease to exist. However, unlike with a physical for the fight. For instance, a fight for survival with struggle, there is no element of unilaterality in physical combat does not correspond precisely a duel; on the contrary, it is characterised by a to the essence of corporal fighting, because the mutual agreement between the fighters, once ultimate motivation of the fighter is to prevent both participants are willing to accept the oth- someone else from killing him. The motivation er’s reciprocal attempt to fight for honour. of corporal fighting is inherent in the fight itself insofar as the key element that drives the fight- A duel embraces only one characteristic of corpo- ers is a kind of ethical challenge embodied only ral fighting’s ethical features. It is best to consult by the act of corporal fighting. What is this ethi- a dictionary to understand the essential scope cal challenge? To repeat: it is that of overcom- and cultural relativity of the concept of honour. ing the opponent while avoiding being overcome. According to the Brazilian Aurélio Dictionary, hon- What this overcoming involves precisely will be our is a ‘sense of dignity that leads the individual

358 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

to seek and deserve all consideration’. A further hostile element in corporal fighting? Such a limit step towards understanding honour can be taken is given by the objective conversion of growing by reading philosopher Kwame Anthony Appiah, hostility in strikes that dissolve the reciprocal eth- for whom ‘the heart of psychology of honour – ical nature of corporal fighting. When a hostility – the giving and receiving of respect – is already in which is exclusively psychic in the beginning, i.e. you as it is in every normal human being, however subjectively experienced – undergoes this objec- enlightened and advanced’ [53, p. xix]. tive conversion, there is a transition toward the reification of the other party into an entity as a Honour is thus a sense of self-esteem, a feel- result of disaffection with the exchanges, lead- ing of being worthy of respect. The perception ing to strokes expressing hostility. Therefore, of someone that is attacked on his self-esteem the limit lies between a possible hostility that is deserving physical combat repair may lead presfrontier itself in a contained manner – com- to real combat. The first possibility of real com- posed and tolerant – and a hostility concretely bat is presented by a simple, immediate attack, expressed in combative action – unrestrained. which would be closer to a street fight movement (struggle). A second possibility is a challenge to What about hostility in ‘combat sport’? In this engage in a physical confrontation which equates case, the limit is institutionally regulated with to a propositional mediation between the dam- rules that are guaranteed by the referee, which age to honour and a confrontation with restor- control the conduct of the participants. Anyway, ative intent. This propositional mediation appears for combat sports, from a psychological point as the structuring temporal element distinguish- of view, the limits of contained hostility must ing a duel from a fight. Combat for the sake of be respected. The psychological dynamic inher- honour ‒ a more permanent manifestation of ent to combat experiences is the determinant in one’s self-esteem ‒ is different from circumstan- developing the subjectivity of a fighter and is one tial combat as it is triggered by an emotional reac- of the most important points in communities of tion that, in another situation, depending on the different combat practitioners, whether sportive mood of the offended, could be more easily miti- or non-sportive. Hostility should not become gated. The value that fulfils a given notion of liv- objective because the event would cease to be ing honour varies enormously and can be even a sporting event. In sporting events, the essen- highly individualised, independent of institution- tial condition of not being openly and objectively alised social codes: ‘to say people have honour is hostile sustains its sporting nature and maintains to say that they are entitled to respect accord- the practice within institutionalised rules, ideally ing to the codes of their honour worlds’ [53, p. aiming to restrict violence to within the confines 31]. In spite of this variation, honour absolutely of those rules. In theoryfromo remain within needs to be defended, under penalty of living in the sporting ethos, combatants cannot express shame, since ’shame is the feeling appropriate to corporally or morally the outright hostility that one’s own dishonourable behaviour’ [53, p. 31]. would arise from strokes and offences devoid To avoid a life of shame and to make patent his of the reciprocal nature of corporal fighting. This, purest intentions, the dishonoured dis- however, does not mean that corporal fightingand plays the interior of his venter. The localisation combat sports do not feature aggressiveness, an of the soul is attributed to the venter, exposed energetic element crucial to those who fight but in the sepukku, the suicide ritual known as hara- not the same as hostility. kiri [21]. One final distinguishing characteristic of the Since some kind of hostility is essential to ‘phys- various forms of physical confrontation is con- ical struggle’ and ‘duels’ – the demand for resti- cerned play. This is similar to corporal fighting in tution for an affront to dignity – it can also be that, unlike a duel, the motivational experience asked whether hostility is a necessary or possible focuses on playful grace rather than on the deter- element in corporal fighting and ‘combat sports’. mined challenge that characterises combat. One Hostility is certainly not a necessary element in must, therefore, recognise that physical confron- these phenomena, although it should be treated tation can be marked by playfulness, as in chil- as a possibility within certain limits. These lim- dren’s fighting games, but also occasionally as in its delineate the boundaries of corporal fighting ‘combat’ in which the disparity between combat- and combat sports as distinguishable units within ants is such that a real challenge for the partici- consciousness flow. What, then, is the limit of the pants does not arise. One of the characteristics

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 359 Original Article

of these play-fights is that participants may delib- an agreement between the parties, made possi- erately swap positions, putting themselves in a ble by a time lag between the act that insulted situation of inferiority or superiority without this the honour and the fight itself. being a determinant of any dispute because in these games the purpose is not to define a win- While the duel does not have the reciprocal ethi- ner and a loser. If the definition of victory and cal feature of corporal fighting, this does not mean defeat has important consequences for the par- that it is less ethical but only that it is consti- ticipants, the play in question gives rise to another tuted by another ethic. Through this, the duel- phenomenon, namely, physical struggle of some list’s moral strength is evident because it is an sort. By now we have distinguished some of the ethics in which, ultimately, the duellist’s honour phenomena that are essential to the general field is placed above life itself or, at least, above physi- of physical combat and which approach the phe- cal well-being. Thus, in a duel, combat is a means nomenon that this research is trying to explain, of achieving another goal that is not restricted namely, corporal fighting. As anticipated, what to fighting itself, namely, that of defending one’s constitutes the phenomenon of corporal fighting honour. The eidetic analysis performed herein is the gravitational centre of martial arts, and this puts brackets around those particular situations plays a decisive role in the analyses carried out that lead both participants to defend their hon- below. In the phenomenological reduction pro- our, without dealing with the justice or injustice cess performed below, the various forms of phys- of any action. In short, the duel is a physical con- ical combat have not been treated as objects and frontation motivated by the defence of honour so have not been regarded from an objective per- and whose ritualisation implies the possibility of spective. Instead, the objects have given way to the opponent also defending himself. the phenomena, that is, they have given way to how these occurrences are revealed to conscious- By this definition, the duel is submitted to the ness. One can consider here the first-person per- prevailing notion of honour, to what is felt to be spective [54-56] of someone – the author or the an affront to dignity. Thus, the concepts of hon- reader – who assumes the attitude of those who our are so flexible from culture to culture, and witness such phenomena intuitively filling them eventually within the same culture so relative from the descriptions in progress in this paper. in reference to the meaning of its defence, that Thus, with reference to situations experienced other resources, such as rationalisation, political directly or indirectly, remembered or imagined, or pondering, and even self-deception, can aid in described in literary works or presented in mov- the development of a person’s moral and psy- ies, one can assess the adequacy of the essential chological integrity. Thus, to defend one’s hon- description and different manifestations of duels, our can mean eventually to not make use of the fights, games, and struggles. radical device of a duel or even the polemic of a ‘verbal duel’. Attesting the flexibility of the notion The phenomenon of duelling has always shown of honour is not equivalent to weakening its deci- itself to be a matter of honour, whether through sive role for mankind, nor to understanding hon- the celebrated cape-and- novels of our as a feeling that is easily interchangeable. The Alexandre Dumas, such as The Count of Monte duellist puts honour above his physical integrity Cristo, the epic Homeric duel between Hector and, ultimately, above his life – knowing very well and Achilles, the samurai stories of Miyamoto on behalf of what he is fighting. However, refer- Musashi (1584–1645), or the history of duel- ring to the historical idea of a duel to the death ling in in the sixteenth and sev- between gentlemen, Appiah [53] shows that the enteenth centuries. Even defeat can be regarded duel became considered a source of shame rather as honourable, even if painful – think of Hector than a source of honour, a change of opinion that in Troy – because it remains expressive of the took centuries to occur. The process through fight for dignity. Reflecting a value that, socio- which the duel was led to infamy and elimina- logically, is typically organised by traditional aris- tion took place thanks to a moral revolution – tocracies, duellists do not act unilaterally, which and as such, quickly – dissociating the repair would be shameful for those who live in accor- of self-respect from the fight to the death [53]. dance with the codes that govern this type of However, a duel may be considered as mean- confrontation, but ritualise the fight as a defence ing to honour one’s own life. In a certain way, it of honour. This ritualisation is essentially charac- gives sense to life. This can mean saving a life in terised by the fact that the duel is preceded by a naked sense, i.e. the biological sense, but also

360 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

saving a life in a moral sense within the concep- cases, as shown by Sánchez Garcia [57] and by tion of human dignity. Melo and Barreira [58], the intensity of rampant blows, which is defined by the specificity of the The struggle, in its turn, may even include a sense interaction between practitioners, corresponds of honour, as a hostile reaction is not without to a loss of control and the emergence of vio- injury to the dignity of the subject. Its immedi- lence. Sánchez Garcia [57] points out that the cri- ately reactive character, however, differentiates terion of loss of control is given by the notion of the experience of struggling from that of the duel. normal practice, institutionally defined and lived By immediately reactive character, we mean not a by experienced practitioners. chronological immediateness (one can feel hostil- ity before a struggle), but a kind of reaction that Therefore, the essence of corporal fighting lies in makes the hostility and the physical attack ‘iden- identifying the intentionality of a body that is also tical’. When a struggle occurs, any other media- a subject. What is this intentionality and what is tion happening prior to or at that moment ‒ a the relevance of situating the body of the fighter reflexive or persuasive one, for instance ‒ falls as a subject? Briefly, it has already been men- into a separate hostility coming from the physical tioned that corporal fighting requires the chal- attack, experienced as a physical urge to act. This lenge of physically overcoming another while reactivity to the other is imbued with a hostility avoiding being overcome. The inherent challenge that suggests the loss of otherness and thus loss of corporal fighting reveals part of its intention- of the other as a subject with values and freedom. ality but hides its deeper meaning, which is its It is worthwhile to appreciate the significance essential meaning. It has been clarified that what of this loss of freedom: physical confrontation defines a fight is the fact that, in it, ‘the bodies means the physical overcoming of an opponent, of the fighters remain the target, as an object, an overcoming that corresponds to cancelling his and objective of the actions’ [41, p. 20]. From immediate freedom of action in the world. This is this simple and structural insight, it is possible corporeal action and is well illustrated by strug- to penetrate into its intentional sphere, stress- gles where the aim is to shut someone up. This ing some consequences for the phenomenology lived experience of being taken by hostility puts of combat. The first of them concerns the adver- the other into an objectified state, whose charac- sary: those who have an opponent’s body as their teristic is to be reduced to a negative and threat- target also have, simultaneously, their own body ening presence. At the moment when the subject as the target of their adversary. We should reflect takes the initiative in a physical struggle, even if on what this means: The implication is that the only instantly, there is no sense of respect toward purpose is not just to or stop the oppo- the other. The intention is to nullify otherness ‒ nent’s body, as the target, but also to avoid hav- the other objectified as negative and threaten- ing one’s own body hit or stopped as the target of ing ‒ even if it happens for a very brief moment, one’s adversary. When considering the purpose which it does most of the time. Even if the strug- of physically overcoming the opponent, that is, gle is followed by repentance or justification having him as a target, the corollary to that must for the event, which would encompass a moral also be acknowledged, namely, the purpose of reflection on the experience, it does not change not being overcome by one’s opponent. It fol- anything with regard to the essence of the phe- lows that an objective reading of the fight, that nomenon that occurs, unreflectively, at the time is, an external reading, is inadequate; the chal- it is happening, i.e. without mediation between lenge arises of understanding the fight regarding hostility and attack. This does not mean that the its own intentionality. fight and all hostility correlated to it occur in a thoughtless or irrational manner since every fight The second possible point to consider in order has its meaning, but that the attack is primarily to comprehend Figueiredo’s definition [41], at considered a direct expression of hostility. its core, is that the fight is not against a body, but against another fighter (who, of course, Phenomenally, the struggle looks like an event is not disembodied). Naturally, the fighter is a lacking a degree of corporal control. It is not by person. Nonetheless, the fight occurs against chance that when a martial arts practitioner is the fighter rather than against the person. If seised by hostility so that the intensity of the inverted, the circumstances would characterise blows become uncontrolled, witnesses often say it not as a fight, but as a conflict, which, in its that the match turned into a street fight. In such turn, can be a struggle (brawl), self-defence, or an

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 361 Original Article

instrumental offensive combat procedure, a duel. been met. Thus, when there is no reciprocity in However, what is decisive in this particular oppo- a physical confrontation, it can be considered a sitional intersubjective relationship is the range form of confrontation motivated by hostility or by of intentional actions carried out by the partici- an offensive physical attack that occurs regard- pants’ bodies. less of the victim’s consciousness; thus, there is no corporal fighting. In order to reach a description that adequately covers the full arc of corporal fighting, it is still Phenomenological apprehension tries to necessary to determine the intended mean- approach the phenomenon exactly as it presents ing of what is objectively referred to as physi- itself to intuition, and within limits, it presents cal overcoming. The intended meaning, in terms to intuition. Figuratively, it can be argued that of lived experience, does not correspond to that the phenomenon ‘speaks about’ itself, but only if natural attitude in which the opponent would be one assumes an appropriate attitude of listening. grasped only as a physical entity to be overcome, Briefly, when the phenomenon of corporal fighting i.e. grasped in a strictly physical way. As indicated is allowed to ‘speak’ about itself, its phenomenal by earlier assertions, it does not eliminate the fact features are immediately apparent, although rel- that the determination of the fight is physical, but atively enigmatic. As previously pointed out, the it highlights the fact that this physicality is inher- interaction of the combatants, characterised by ently subjective because it is the physical body displacements, defences, ’s, submission of a subject. Furthermore, the idea of physical holds, kicking, and hand strikes, develops through overcoming does not reveal the specificity of this the mutual attempts to restrict the operative overcoming, because it is not, for example, a kind mobility of the other subject’s body, and to frus- of physical elimination. Once this negative read- trate his or her same intentions, thereby deter- ing of corporal fighting, that is, a reading clarified mining the phenomenal aspects of the body and of the shortcomings of some descriptions, has the operative fighting. In such a development, been carried out, we can move on to a positive it is possible to understand how the actions are reading. So how do we describe corporal fighting ethically determined by the condition of both in its full scope and specificity? subjects accepting the challenge.

In corporal fighting, the goal is to restrict the oper- There is still a point to be considered: since duel ative mobility of the corporal subject, the oppo- is defined as fighting as a question of honour, nent, as well as to frustrate his or her identical does a corporal fight not involve honour? The intentions, thus determining the phenomenal honour of the fighter lives in his attitude, in his and operative dimensions of corporal fighting, by posture towards himself in facing the fight. His different kinds, uses, and styles of displacement, honour consists of a self-value, an effort to cor- , grappling, submission holding, kicking, responding to his own expectation regarding and striking. the performance toward the combat. The ques- tion of honour in corporal fighting is motivated These intentional goals are ethically deter- by the fighter himself rather than by an offender mined by the condition of being able, fully, to or challenger. Therefore, in spite of implicating make a combatant the centre of a corporal chal- the adversary, the challenge of corporal fighting lenge2 and to know that the opponent is doing is not centred on the other, as in the duel. In cor- the same; these conditions lead both combat- poral fighting, the honour is centred on the fighter ants to accept the challenge. When there is no himself, corresponding to the combative posture reciprocity in terms of consciousness or willing- emulated by the fight, expressing a self-value of ness to restrict the operational mobility of the the subject in action. opponent ‒ that is, if the intention to limit the other’s freedom of movement through physical The qualification of the opponent fighter affects dominance is not shared by both subjects ‒ the the level of the challenge directly and so inter- essential conditions of corporal fighting have not feres with the expectations of performance and attitude, i.e. the honour challenge of fighting. The challenge faced by the fighter to correspond to 2  In cases where the basis of a corporal challenge is not the self-placed expectations will be modulated the challenge itself but another motivation ‒ such as hostility or honour ‒ then the phenomena are matters and optimised by personal tendencies which of physical struggle and duel. come out as lived experiences. As the practice of

362 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

a martial art presumes the existence of a commu- self-preservation behaviour, which may pro- nity, the experiences in question are intertwined tect the person against affronts of their integ- with the culture of this martial art and with the rity, freedom, health and life’ [59, p. 50]. Another fighter’s peers, especially his masters, who are objective definition says that ‘Self-defence is the models for his self-placed expectations. In some capability to counteract one attacker as well as circumstances, the challenge will be facing his a group of them, who do not observe any rules’ fear. In others, the challenge becomes into self- [60, p. 24]. As argued previously, it is necessary indulgence, uncontrolled aggressiveness, negli- to transcend external and objective definitions in gence, the absence of tenacity, etc. The fighter’s order to deeply penetrate these phenomena, in sense of honour also includes his understanding their intentional consciousness. Being willing and of how his behaviour can be moral in the face of ready (prepared) for self-defence is not the same defeat or victory. Therefore, the sense of honour as having the intention to enter into combat, but required to fight rests on the challenges lived by means knowing the manner in which to prevent, each one, which will renew the motivation inher- deter, and stop a physical attack. With regard ent in the fight. However, if no challenge exists in to the last item, to interrupt a physical attack the fight, no question of honour will be evoked. against oneself, against another person, or, in cer- Then, respecting a wide myriad of experiences tain circumstances, against property, leads back and intensities, something materialises out of cor- to corporal fighting as the only appropriate con- poral fighting that necessarily constitutes a pro- dition for a person’s learning and development cess of self-knowledge. This process has martial of skills. Practising with someone by simulating arts as an existential model of confrontation. It attack situations is necessary for promoting pos- is guided by the emulation of a sense of hon- sible responses with defensive intent or, to a cer- our, encompassing a sense of self-value, which, tain degree, with a counter-attack feature, thus in its turn, is about the attitude assumed dur- making the means of action readily available for ing a fight. Once fighting’s essential experiences the person. This will happen through the practice have been developed, every martial art must be of ‘exercises designed for composite but specific grasped as an existential tradition. We are ever preparation for self-defence’, i.e. through ‘defen- closer to a phenomenological understanding of sive training fights and control fights’ [60, p.25]. what a martial art is. We will not be so, however, without prior analysis of two peculiar combative Therefore, defending yourself from a physi- phenomena: self-defence and instrumental offen- cal attack is not a ‘corporal fight’, but it may be sive combat. The danger of these form of com- the use oflearned resources in a corporal fight. bat largely distances it from play fighting. Their However, combat occurring as self-defence has severity does not make self-defence and instru- an essence apart from other combative forms. mental offensive combat identical to a struggle Its motivational act is morally loaded ‒ it can be (brawl) or duel. Entering into hand-to-hand com- filled with a sense of honour ‒ but it is essen- bat by necessity and against one’s own will cir- tially defensive, not combative. For comprehend- cumscribe the lived experience of self-defence. ing its non-combative nature, it is still necessary to take into account the circumstances in which a combative (re)action consists of self-defence. The lived experience here is equivalent to a response SELF-DEFENCE: A NON-COMBATIVE to an attack. To be involved in an attack on one- INTENTION AS ETHICAL PARADIGM self, or to something or someone for whom the As proposed by Del Vecchio [59], self-defence subject feels responsible, is necessarily to be is significantly more than merely using combat emotionally affected by an intentional operating techniques. Self-defence, firstly, allows one to movement of returning the attack with the aim anticipate and avoid situations in which there is of its discontinuation. This defensive attack does a risk of violence or when this risk is unavoid- not imply equivalence, i.e. returning the attack able, to be cautious and, ultimately, defend them- with the same emotion and using the same cor- selves physically. Harasymowicz and Kalina [60] poral action, which would lead to the progres- approach self-defence from a perspective that sion of violence; rather, emotional mobilisation is ‘includes certain categories of preventive mea- needed for the occurrence of the reaction. This sures, verbal counteractions, as well as the is not an eminently logical intentional movement, technique of self-defence in the narrow sense’ but an affective and inter-corporal one. [60, p. 20]. It is, in all cases, ‘defensive and

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 363 Original Article

The limit of the return is also crucial for defining attacks are excluded from the context of a legit- the essence of combat in self-defence; it deals imate defence. The existence of a certain tem- with stopping the attack as well as the dan- poral interval between the aggression and the ger of its continuation. Therefore, self-defence attack may characterise revenge and not defence. will depend on the extension of the danger and This relates to the currentness of the aggression, determination of the offender. Even killing can be which also includes the imminence of the attack a proportional response to an attack, constituting as characterising the response as self-defensive. legitimate self-defence. However, an intentional Attacks from police are supposed to be fair, and if limit that marks combat in self-defence resides this is the case, the response to this kind of attack in the emergency and effectiveness of inten- does not fit the definition of self-defence. The tional acts that characterise properly a brawl. In response must be necessary, i.e. an alternative addition to a defensive return aiming to stop an response, one other than fighting, may not legit- attack and any danger, if the subject is assailed imise the combat as self-defensive. If the answer by a degree of hostility that blinds or impairs his is more aggressively intense than the attack, the conscience with regard to the offender, inducing inversion of roles could characterise revenge. The his reification as occurring in the lived experience voluntarism of the answer concerns the control of a brawl, the defence becomes an attack and of its results, i.e. the injury caused by the defen- the combat becomes a quarrel. Therefore, the sive action. This presumes a high domain of the intentional return of self-defence is always risky used techniques of the body [63]. to exceed in an offence that restricts the capac- ity of recognising the other, transforming into In the ideal democratic society, it is fair to postu- a disproportional reaction to the danger of the late that the idea of a legally delineated self-de- attack. Thus, the boundaries of an appropriate, fence matches the ethical paradigm guiding the intentional return to self-defence require a sig- universal conduct of martial arts practitioners in nificant level of self-control. Interestingly, it has a civil context. This paradigm suggests that, out- been demonstrated that decreased states of hos- side the context of combative practice, the prac- tility and aggressiveness and increased assertive- titioner should sustain a non-combative intent, ness and confidence are associated with learning which also involves the development of skills to self-defence [61]. Similarly, a decrease in fear in prevent conflicts and risks, as well as assume a facing hostile situations has been determined to personal posture of deterring the use of violence be an effect of training in self-defence [62]. as a mean to solve conflicts.3 There is a consistent motivational thread ‒ not an arbitrary connection Thus, besides physical defence, self-defence ‒ between the corporal fighting experience and embraces feelings, attitudes, and behaviours the psychological condition required to exercise related to precautions against risk. Self-defence the ethics of self-defence. The continued prac- goes through not only objective detection of sit- tice of corporal fightinggives the subject the abil- uational dangers but also a certain degree of sen- ity to respond physically and emotionally, i.e. to sitivity and social skills to discern and possibly have physical and psychological control. It is sum- deter others’ offensive intentions. Self-defence marised as an integral self-control experience, is a question of something broad, not restricted superior to the condition that this same person to technical issues but that embraces humanis- would have if not practised. tic education [59]. In spite of peculiarities, this conduct is also the Legally, self-defence have contours and well-es- one expected from various security forces, pri- tablished conditions. Cazalbou [63] discrimi- vate or public, especially the police. Unlike the nates in the French jurisprudence the criteria military, security forces have formations and for defining the aggression and response with training that are not oriented to physical attack which a combative action is fitted as a legitimate and counterattack; according to the law, they defence, a juridical correlation of self-defence: only defend citizens and property. the attack must be real, recent, and unfair; the answer must be necessary, proportional, and voluntary. Being real means there should be a clear danger, the threat of attack or the accom- 3 The cultural tradition of martial arts points to the exis- tence of this gain of self-control, and this efficiency plishment of an attack, not only the presenti- tends to justify them. Much empirical research sup- ment of an attack sensed by the victim; verbal ports this.

364 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

Instrumental offensive combat order to protect themselves, to subdue, compel, Being neither struggle, duel, play fighting, corpo- or destroy the other, for an instrumental reason, ral fighting, nor self-defence, instrumental offen- i.e. to reach a calculated aim. The intention of sive combat has the simple intention to attack protecting themselves, to some extent, is a con- someone, for any reason other than that previ- dition for combat to occur. To enter into com- ously considered as fight or duel. This combat bat, even knowing that the attack will most likely aims for submission (surrender), physical paraly- result in the opponent’s death, is different from sis (applying keys and bottlenecks, causing loss a suicide attack (kamikaze), in which, effectively, of consciousness or harm), or death of the oppo- there is no fighting but mutual destruction. nent, to annul the attacked person. Instrumental offensive combat is not motivated by a ques- What is a martial art? tion of personal honour regarding the attacked person, nor by a hostile intemperate emotional The idea of a kind of martial art that does not outbreak. Differently, than a duel, there is no rit- involve corporal fightinghas already been rejected, ualisation that would imply the possibility of the because corporal fightingis central to martial arts. opponent defending himself. Differently, than a Nonetheless, it remains to be seen how this cen- struggle, hostility here is not reactive (immediate), trality, stated above but not justified, arises. That but a calculated attack approach. physical combat is essential to martial arts is not questioned. Why do we not just settle for this For the purpose of the phenomenological anal- observation to define a martial art? The reason ysis, the empirical motivation for instrumental is that this would keep the phenomenon vague offensive combat should be excluded. The anal- and indistinct, which is what we want to avoid. ysis needs to be done regardless of how the com- According to our previous analyses, physical com- bat is judged, i.e. whether it is correct or not, fair bat can take the forms of struggle (brawl), duel, or unfair, valuable or worthless; what is relevant is play, self-defence, instrumental offensive combat, to grasp its pure intentionality. Then, instrumen- or corporal fighting, each with its own intentional tal offensive combat concerns criminal or mili- horizon. Are all of these implicit in the definition tary actions, for example, actions that feature a of martial art? The answer is no, and this is the calculated intention of attacking. Robbers, ter- postulation supported by the present analysis. rorists and special military forces undertake this kind of combat. Its purpose usually does not lead Indeed, the following question must be answered: to a fight properly, although having as a method is it conceivable that a form of martial art may to show or make direct use of the force. Thus, evolve spontaneously, without implying continu- the protagonist of offensive instrumental combat ous practice? The answer is surely ‘no’. All martial aims to neutralise the target, preferably before arts necessarily imply training in corporal fighting. a fight happens. However, the fact that the If there is no training, there is no martial art phe- attacked party can react and enter into physical nomenon, but, at best, a simulacrum of martial combat may lead the protagonist of the attack, art or its idea.4 by using instrumental calculation, to anticipate this possibility, assuming an intentional combat- ive position. 4 It is prudent to consider that corporal fighting ‒ the essence of which has been analysed above ‒ is not lim- In contrast to this, when a statement between ited to actual physical confrontation but is essentially the involved parties is presumed, war is equiva- enabled by the motor-intention emergence of con- frontation. It can thus occur to a subject even when lent to a duel on a large scale. Offensive instru- the opponent is only imaginary, as is the case with mental combat is done without the knowledge corporal combat that is practiced solo. In martial arts, of the opponent, who is actually seen and con- these solo practices involve specified forms, such as the Japanese and the Chinese chuan. They sidered, perceived and thought of, as a target of express motor operations comprising clearly defined the attack: ‘Elite military teams, hostage rescue, defence and attack strategies directed at one or more SWAT and entry teams, as well as criminals, use imaginary opponents. The phenomenological differ- ence between corporal fighting with a real opponent any methods they can, including surprise, supe- and corporal fighting with an imaginary opponent lies in rior numbers, and superior weapons, to disable the factual otherness, effectiveness, and consequences or to force compliance, preferably without the inherent in the former. The latter is engaged in a com- bat that is free of effectiveness and true consequences, need to fight or kill’ [3, p.7]. What, precisely, is both of which are inherent in a physical confrontation the intention here? It is to attack the opponent in with a real opponent.

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 365 Original Article

The training in corporal fighting inherent in martial Corporal fighting, according to the meaning arts connotes, as will be noticed, a determination revealed by intentional analysis, besides being of the phenomenal and ethical dimensions of cor- required for martial arts is a central lived refer- poral fighting. It is quite possible that such training ence for the relationship established between leads the practitioner to subjective experiences fighters. In the modulation of such a relation, that are closer to other phenomena at the periph- psychic variations in hostility can drive the fight- ery of corporal fighting, such as physical struggles ers to the edge of a physical struggle or a duel (brawls), duels, acts of self-defence, and some forms during training, making it too dangerous and/ of recreation activities. Very likely, over the years, or threatening. However, a lack of challenge or trained fighters will have intersubjective experi- threat makes training nothing more than a play- ences, which can be objectively recognised and are ful experience or dilettante practice, or even a peculiar to some of the previously mentioned fringe practice just for fitness. Thus, corporal fightingcan phenomena.5 However, what happens during the be understood as existing in a state of dynamic lived experience of training itself is not a struggle tension along its borders. The rupture of the (brawl), duel, real self-defence, or play. If martial arts boundaries of these lived experiences is gener- are defined in terms of the training they necessarily ated by intentional excesses, such as aggression involve, they are also committed to the aforemen- that becomes hostility, or intentional deficiency, tioned essence of corporal fighting, in the event that such as the absence of challenges. This intersub- physical struggles (brawls), duels, real instrumental jective challenge constitutes the essence of fight- offensive combat, real self-defence situations, and ing, and its absence can be motivated by fear, play cannot be properly trained.6 negligence, or whatever else. Every fight has its own dynamic tension, which is constituted by the What is achieved with training, namely, the acqui- fighters’ reciprocity and, occasionally, the violent sition and improvement of the fighter’s abilities, loose of reciprocity. can be applied to several physical combat situa- tions ‒ such as combat sports and the learning The psychic variations experienced by the prac- of a martial art form ‒ as well as to situations not titioner of a martial art form while in combat strictly classified as corporal fighting per se, but as takes him or her into the psychological states of physical struggles, duels, or forms of instrumental a duel, physical struggle, instrumental offensive offensive combat, self-defence, and play. In this combat, self-defence, or play. Eventually, some sense, training may even aim at the realisation psychological states materialise operatively in of these other actions that do not correspond to hostile attacks or recreational practices, modify- actual corporal fighting, such as physical struggle, ing the combat-effective conditions. Indeed, an but the training itself does not involve a physical objective condition pertaining to brawls, duels, struggle (brawl). Such experiences are intention- self-defence, and play is established. This descrip- ally different; one can be an experience that pre- tion of phenomena and their boundaries does not pares for future action, whereas the other can be make for definitive outlines, but rather forms the a hostile or playful act. foreground of lived experiences, whose central presence and effectiveness are the determinants of the phenomena, without excluding the pos- 5 Some interesting ethnographic examples are described sibility of a simultaneous occurrence of differ- by Sánchez Garcia [57], and some grasped by using nar- ratives in first person by Melo and Barreira [58]. ent lived experiences. The occurrence of these 6 Representations of those forms of physical conflict that phenomena is therefore dependent on the cor- can be rehearsed or trained are excluded. This kind of relation between the ‘subjective’ (psychic lived training does not have any bearing on the effectiveness of the challenge among the players; rather, it deals with experience) and the ‘objective’ (effective corpo- the challenge of representation itself and its improve- ral action) facets that occur simultaneously. A ment. Recreational play, even if repeated many times, fighter may feel overtaken by hostility, but fight- as in a training program, can retain its essential rec- reational criteria, without which the same would be ing itself is not determined by this; indeed, fight- performed mechanically and be devoid of its essential ing is designed to avoid the accomplishment of grace. The training can be mechanical, although the hostile action. real meaning of the above-mentioned training forms, which are exemplified by tai chi chuan and kata, are neither mere representations nor mechanically expe- On the other hand, a fighter with no hostile rienced training forms. Even if the opponent is imagi- intent may act with an intensity that is objec- nary, these training forms can be subjectively lived as expressions of corporal fighting, not in itself, but as if tively understood as inappropriate for a fight, in corporal fighting. either because the fighter violates normative

366 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

standards or because the limits of combative case of self-defence, instrumental offensive com- intensity have been exceeded in the eyes of the bat, struggle, or duel, the centrality of the effec- opponent. As noted in both examples, there is tive presence of lived experience framing the no simultaneity between subjective and objec- other is the determinant (i.e. the essential con- tive correlates that would constitute an actual stituent) of corporal fighting. Thus, given that struggle (brawl). Without the option provided by training is an essential element of martial arts, the eidetic reduction to identify hostility as a key its practice is an experience whose intentional factor in the struggle (brawl), it would not be pos- horizon is delineated primarily by the layer per- sible to describe the essentiality of the different taining to corporal fighting. Even if this horizon is lived experiences of physical combat. It would aimed at and nourished by other purposes, every- also affect the recognition that hostility may thing on it is dispensable while the essential ele- emerge in corporal fighting because it is a psycho- ment of the intentional structure of the martial logical rather than an empirical condition in which art, corporal fighting, remains. one experiences the struggle (brawl). Maintaining the spirit of corporal fighting ‒ the fighting spirit‒ The intentionality of corporal fighting previously as the central axis of the lifeworld is in keeping described is, in its turn, essential to Martial Arts. with the principles of any martial art form. This As should be noted, the descriptions have made is not to say that martial arts do not have differ- an eidetic move from an essential level to a pos- ent aims to those of corporal fighting, however. sibly empirical level, that is, located in possible This is down to time and place. Fights are defined existences, a move that occurs especially when according to the situation, by the intentional field using real examples. The assertion above corre- of the combatants. sponds to the general idea of martial arts and does not exclude the possibility that certain mar- The purpose of practising a martial art may be tial arts lose their characteristics if the elements for possible participation in a duel, as instru- of hostility and danger are removed or if they are mental offensive combat or self-defence against converted into a struggle or duel. One can sug- a physical attack. According to these goals, mar- gest that narratives in which struggles and duels tial arts practice, in temporal and psychological modulate postures and inspire virtues such as terms, is a preparation, anticipation, for likely sit- courage have historically characterised all mar- uations. Although simulated, this corporeal fight- tial arts. It is unreasonable to infer that a martial ing is a quite real combat. The mutual availability art is the same thing as a struggle or a duel. As to corporal fighting is a requirement of fighters a lived experience, the fighting spirit is the per- for simulating confrontations with other kinds sonal tension pertaining to the challenge of cor- of confrontation by using embodied imagina- poral fighting, which avoids being dragged down tion.7 Practising martial arts is corporeal fight- by the psychic state corresponding to the strug- ing as if it was a duel, as if it was a brawl as if it gle and its lack of control, or by the complacency was instrumental offensive combat as if it was a that would reduce the challenge, or by a fear so self-defence situation. Although it requires the strong that it hinders the confrontation. use of the imagination, corporal fighting is not the same thing as playing in a duel, playing in a The attitude of the fighting spirit opens up the brawl, attacking, or self-defending. The anticipa- lifeworld to the availability of the challenge that tion and simulation, which constitute a kind of emerges as a corporal readiness for combat. It presentification posed by these goals, mean that, is not an arbitrary launching into fights but a psychologically, different lived experiences arise readiness to accept and respond to the mutual simultaneously. Which ones are determinants to intention to challenge. Therefore, invoking the be included in the practice of martial arts? Even fighting spirit means responding to the avail- with anticipated presentification and a simulated ability of the other. In this attention to the other and modulation of one’s own presence resides the ethical aspect of corporal fighting. It is nec- 7 About the simulated combat subject, see the empirical essary to consider also that this response is an research of Broomé [64] that makes ‘a phenomenologi- cal study of a police academy cadet´s lived experiences ethical duty to one’s existence ‒ to respond to of role-play-simulated scenarios of lethal encounters violent attacks, hostile attacks that do not com- and deadly force training’ (p. 153). As noticed, ‘When ply with the assumption of intentional reciproc- the participants had gained control over the simulated incident, they noticed that their anxiety diminished and ity, which is peculiar to corporal fighting. This their surreal perceptions became normal again’ (p. 154). does not mean that the ideal of the fighting

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 367 Original Article

spirit is to be disposed to fight in any situation, typification of the ethical dimension of corporal for instance, to accept challenges such as duels. fighting, namely, through a typical cultural code Instead, the attack presupposes a reaction to of conduct that is necessarily reflected in com- avoid being transformed into a victim of violence. bat attitudes. The promptness of the fighting spirit inspires atti- tudes and gestures that are formalised in martial While the idea of an ethical code is included in arts, providing a structure endowed with per- this typical dimension, it makes more sense to sistence in their phenomenal and ethical dimen- talk here of an ethos, which is to say a broad code sions. In turn, this formalisation favours the of conduct, a way in which human beings relate availability of the fighting spirit in the lifeworld. to each other. The ethical dimension of any mar- This is the sense of honour intrinsic to corpo- tial art form includes the conduct of the self to real fighting and, as mentioned before, developed itself, the way of being a self in the world, a way in martial arts. Here, fighting for honour is not of being present among other people, a way of identical to the combat for the honour of a duel, positioning oneself in relationships, and a ‘sub- where combat is a manner of solving a conflict jective process’ developed through body-to-body of honour, although this must exist in order for experiences [65]. Thus, the enhanced experiential corporal fighting to occur. reference implies a moral dimension, culturally articulated ‒ and commonly religiously artic- Nevertheless, no martial art form is solely defined ulated ‒ with regard to forms of conduct that, by the most elementary meaning of corporal among other things, avoid certain types of con- fighting, namely, the mutual intention between frontation and reaffirm ways of facing them. In combatants to restrict the mobility of the oppo- the absence of a commitment to the enhanced nent while avoiding being restricted in his/her ethical dimension, there can be no martial art, own mobility. Each martial art form comprises a only systematised corporal fighting. Likewise, method, with attack-and-defence patterns. Such without a commitment to the systematic com- a method aims to fulfil a combative intention that bat motor-phenomenal dimension, there can be corresponds to the formalisation of a corporal no martial art; only morality or spirituality per- system. To approach this system solely on the sists. These two dimensions are constitutively physical plane is to lose its intrinsic sensibility and and co-dependently interlaced, bodily express- perceptive order, the latter of which is related to ing both the superficial and profound aspects of the apprehension and recognition of the differ- a martial art form. ent martial art forms and intersubjective combat dynamics and corporal positioning in the world. DISCUSSION These elements are dealt with adequately by a consideration of the phenomenal features of The analyses were done here make it possible to each martial art, that is, as they appear to the define precisely corporal fighting and martial arts senses. We might talk of aesthetics of their forms, (budo). These definitions take into ethical con- although aesthetics here does not imply the idea sideration criteria related to the mutual dispo- of beauty as a central component, even if the cor- sition and motivation to fight. In addition, they poral domain of experienced practitioners can clarify the nature of the objects under examina- be regarded as beautiful when compared to the tion in terms of their cultural, technical, and eth- lack of corporal control demonstrated by begin- ical aspects. From here, it is possible to question ners.8 The aesthetical aspect is reflected in the some of the meanings and scope regarding the motor-operative capacity to restrict the mobility explanation of this phenomenon, from a philo- of others through hits, projections, strangleholds, sophical, scientific, and practical point of view, and so on, as well as through defensive manoeu- by taking into account the pertinent literature. vres. The formal systematisation of the aesthetic dimension of corporal fightingdefines one facet of From a philosophical point of view, it is interest- martial arts; the other is defined by the enhanced ing to appeal directly to Husserlian reflections, with which these investigations try to align, in a 8 In Japanese budo, argues Sasaki: ‘Techniques are con- manner that can situate them within the perspec- trolled by standards of beauty. The technical move- tive of the phenomenological school. The philos- ments have to have artistic value. This is not beauty dictating function, but the function and utility of a opher states: ‘It can be seen quite generally that technique installing beauty into the form’ [25, p. 48]. there are many kinds of objectivities which defy

368 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

all psychologistic and all naturalistic misinter- these cultural phenomena. This is clear in the pretations’ [19, p.421]. The conceptual failure distinction that qualifies the different forms of of defining fighting or martial arts accuses how combat. The ontological foundation of this pos- exact is the Husserlian diagnosis and demon- sibility resides in the phenomenon of empathy. strates how certain approaches are equivalent to Empathy, as rigorously analysed by Husserl [70] naturalists or psychologising attempts, to which and Edith Stein [71], is a special lived experi- these phenomena do not curve. In the literature, ence. Ales Bello stressed that ‘by means of this these attempts define martial arts as Asiatic [23], we recognise the common humanity within our- historical [42, 39], or by physical particularities selves and others’ [51, p. 11]. Thus, empathy [20], as well as ritualistic, mimetic, metaphorical is the basis of the constitution of all possible or modified expression of a supposed real con- shared objectivity, what Husserl designates the flict [41, 44, 40, 3],9 ‘unity of higher order’, the identical intersubjec- tive thing: ‘Its constitution is related to an indef- This happens, argues Husserl, ‘with all types of inite plurality of subjects that stand in a relation objects bearing the value, all practical objects, of “mutual understanding”. The intersubjective all concrete cultural organisations which as hard world is the correlation of the intersubjective realities determine our actual life, the State, for experience, mediated, that is, through “empa- instance, the Church, custom, the law, and so thy”’ [19, p. 420]. forth’ [19, p. 422] and ‘all these objective enti- ties (Objektitäten; in German) must be described In its turn, ‘the living body is thus the instru- in a way they come to be presented according to ment of the encounter between human beings, their fundamental types and their proper order of mutual recognition and the basis for estab- of formation’ [19, p.421, 422]. lishing an interpersonal relationship’ [51, p.12]. Physical combat, an animal phenomenon with Since the time of Husserl, the state was described human specificities, concomitantly universal and in 1925 by Edith Stein [66], the law in 1913 by culturally particularised, corresponds to some Adolf Reinach [67], and, quite recently, arriving of the more concrete, extreme, and elementary at the lived experiences that founded the Church, ways through which empathy, i.e. the recogni- the sacred was described by Angela Ales Bello tion of the other, can effectively be developed [18]. Other cultural phenomena, such as the lit- or become obscure in human relationships. The erary work of art in 1931 [68] and education [69], current analysis demonstrates that an exclu- were analysed, seeking to explicit their funda- sive glance into the physical or the psychologi- mental types and their proper order of formation. cal dimension cannot lead to the comprehension The present analysis tries to be inserted in this of these phenomena. It is in the intersubjective phenomenological way of thinking, in its attempt interweaving of corporal experiences that grasp to describe physical combat, and especially cor- combative experiences, in which the intentional poral fighting and martial arts as objects bearing relationship between two parts will determine value and practicality the kind of action that is going on.

The inter-subjective sphere plays a decisive The general features of a regional ontology, the role in the understanding and constitution of region of physical combat, make evident that cor- poral fighting al place in the study of the sport. 9 Even if is an eidetic analysis, from the point of view of Besides, duel, instrumental offensive combat, and classical phenomenology, the Martínková and Parry self-defence are central to the military sciences categorisation [3] fails for not operating the Epoche, 10 making use of established knowledge rather than sus- are central. For the sake of creating a definition, pend them. This does not reduce the importance of the corporal fighting is the mutual availability of chal- work. Besides, although militating for a phenomeno- lenge between combatants, in which the goal is to logical philosophy of sport, the fact that the authors did not mention phenomenology in the article shows restrict the operative mobility of the corporal sub- that they are aware of the fact that their classification ject, the opponent, as well as to frustrate his or her does not conform to its principles. As argued before, identical intentions. which places their interpretation as psychologist is not the general classification, which is not naturalistic or psychologist, but only the assertion that there is a real fight by necessity and other modified form of combat. Explaining the phenomenon based on a psychological 10 Broomé’s work [64] can be taken as an example. cause, necessarily or not, to define their reality lies on a psychological argument.

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 369 Original Article

This definition retains the ethical criteria, which As argued by Barczyński et al. [72] in the Editorial is described in its essence and related to mutual of Archives of Budo, ‘Any division of sciences and availability, to the motivation for the fight itself. any classification of scientific disciplines and spe- From this definition, it is possible to establish cialties are in some sense imperfect’ [72, p.117]. the general articulation and eidetic connec- So, the editorial preview of the Journal has four tions among the different scientific interests. sections of published articles: Sciences of Martial This is consistent with the defence proposed by Arts, Health Prevention, Philosophy and History, authors such as Cynarski [39], Barczyński et al. which are founded on the conviction that to [72], Figueiredo [41], Krzemieniecki and Kalina restrict the Journal to one privileged part of sci- [73], Kalina [74], Barczyński and Kalina [75], and entific classification would be ‘a contradiction of Martinkóvá and Parry [3]. From different meth- the Budo conception’ [72, p. 119]. By this rea- odological and theoretical perspectives, these son, ‘Necessary is an interdisciplinary approach’ authors are situated in epistemological positions [72, p. 117]. A phenomenology is a potent tool whose dialogue with the phenomenological per- for thinking of the unity of AM&CS phenomena spective presented here is the most fruitful. based on their ontology.

The reductionist approach adopted by Vey [20] As mentioned, the lived experiences that are contrasts explicitly with the phenomenological active and essentially determinants in corporal approach, although not in its primary objective, fighting constitute its operant motor intention- i.e. the idea of scientifically thinking of fighting ality, its apprehension of the other, and its spe- in an integral manner. It is also possible to indi- cific motivation. The presence, absence, or even viduate the technical field of scientific research failure of the intensity will determine whether a that will address the operative dimension of cor- concrete case is or is not a corporal fight. For poral fighting, aiming to identify data and condi- Husserl [19], ‘every description of Essential Being tions for the improvement of different aspects which relates to types of experience provides an of the fight. Some examples, such as the study unconditionally valid norm for the possibilities of athletic training in the areas of biomechan- of empirical existences’ [19, p. 231]. Therefore, ics, physiology, nutrition, epidemiology of inju- for sports psychology (and for military psychol- ries, pedagogy, and psychology, as subjective ogy, in its appropriate contexts), the knowledge processes that favour or disfavour the practitio- here exhibited signals for critical norms to their ner, illustrate the general goal of these technical application, by which the empirical existence of investigations. combat demands a scientifically founded psy- chological know-how. From an interventional This definition of corporal fighting means that perspective, by means of an inter-subjectively the study of its technical aspects is only possible encounter with the practitioner, it is necessary when the discipline is understood in its entirety, to look for his unique and proper conditions, i.e. including its ethical meaning. This dimension i.e. his psychological conditions, to fight effec- will be more openly explored in the fields of his- tively without being carried away by lived expe- tory, sociology, psychology, philosophy, anthro- riences that are improper to corporal fighting. In pology, and so on. The inclusion of subject and this sense, on the trail of a ‘Phenomenological object terms provided by phenomenology also Sport Psychology’, the Husserl’s [19] orienta- means that the presented definition concerns not tion is still assumed; for him, as argued in § 79 only the subjects that practice corporal fighting, of Ideas, ‘phenomenology is the court of appeal but also the researchers who investigate corporal for the fundamental questions of psychology fightingobjectively. Indeed, the terms subject and methodology. The general conclusions which it object ‘presume’ tacitly, that is to say, implicitly, has reached must be recognised and, as occa- that the whole phenomenon includes the con- sion requires, adopted by the psychologists as cept of ‘challenging’ itself, whether lived in the the condition of possibility of all further devel- first or third person, i.e., lived by the fighters and opments of the method in his field’ [19, p. 231]. researchers respectively. This means that, sharing a lived experience within a community research- One might expect that without an awareness of ers have the challenging intention to improve, the distinction between corporal fightingand vio- through scientific knowledge, the conditions that lence, there would be an increased risk of blur- qualify fighters and their practices, of research- ring the boundary between them. Indeed, the ersd self-development. boundary that separates them is categorically

370 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

delineated by the phenomenological transition is, systematised in terms of its own aesthetics between the experience of living the phenom- and ethical aspects. Aesthetics refers to the set enon and the experience of being aware of the of a participant’s actions that is appropriate for phenomenon, which raises awareness of and combat. Ethics refers to the typical attitudes dis- thematises it.11 Revealing the tacit presumption played in practice and in the interaction between makes explicit the practitioners’ and researchers’ practitioners, attitudes that tend to be fixed by ethics, the risk they face in flirting with violence, habits, articulating personal interaction, contem- and the kinds of positions they can assume. poraneously, with the knowledge transmitted by coexistence. The incalculable variety of ways of Thus, ethically, the technical research opera- practising corporal fightingcorresponds to the cul- tively dimensioned in corporal fighting assumes tural diversity of martial arts and the multiplicity an agreement between the fighters for the occur- of its practical and moral guidelines, all of which rence of combat with a sense of respect for the refer to particular times and social contexts but other, which means not to turn him into a thing, never validate the exclusion of the two central nor becoming a violent action. Simultaneously, facets of corporal fighting. To make explicit the objective conditions are given for raising the limits of corporal fightingis capital to understand- technical level of the ethical challenge inherent ing the lived experiences with which their bound- in the fight itself, so that the production of tech- aries are wiped out by violence. nical knowledge can stimulate improvement of the ethical challenge of corporal fighting, once From an empirical point of view, it will be cru- motor control and athletic condition lead to psy- cial, therefore, to understand how these lived chological control. In its turn, investigative com- experiences are cultural and communally regu- prehension of the moral processes intrinsic to the lated among practitioners of different arts and practice of corporal fighting ‒ whether thematic or in different places -as pointed out in the case of not ‒ improves conditions to maintain self-con- capoeira by Melo and Barreira [58]. The cultural trol and so qualify technical performance in the sphere and its values, encompassing the manner motor dimensions of fighting. It favours or dis- by which its practitioners embody these values favours the fighter, thereby providing the chal- also deserve investigation, for instance, by the lenge of fighting and the realisation of technical psychology and anthropology fields, in order to performance. In each case, the field of technical reach an ethical perspective that would be much research, as well as the ethical and cultural fields, more direct and objective than the one attained are focused on one pole of what is commonly by technical and physical studies. understood as objectivity and subjectivity, with no true phenomenological separation between By this point, we have sufficiently stressed that them. The integration of knowledge related to the lack of an appropriate definition of what these poles, either on the part of the practitioner constitutes a ‘martial art’ can lead to the term or the part of researcher provides integrity to the being regarded, erroneously, as a cultural partic- corporal fighting phenomenon. In this sense, the ularity that originated in the East. Perhaps one present postulation assumes the interpretation can assume intuitively that martial arts practitio- proposed by Figueiredo [41], except that here, ners have always understood what it is. Different beyond the hermeneutic puzzle, we indicate the authors around the world who are dedicated to connections that provide the essential integrity the study of martial arts certainly are clear about and continence to the phenomenon of corporal its scope. Italian historian Sergio Raimondo [76] fighting. posited that ‘the so-called martial arts are disci- plines, first of all, dedicated to self-education and Once the corporal fighting is defined, it is possi- not specialisations for the exercise of violence’ ble to move onto defining the second phenome- [76, p. 27]. The list of authors who adopt its scope non to which this investigation is dedicated. The would be virtually endless, so it is easy to find term ‘martial arts’ refers specifically to corporal examples that support the argument that there fighting that is systematised in its totality, that is an essential degree of equivalence between martial arts and budo or wushu. Sasaki stated that 11 This corresponds to being aware of being aware of ‘Ancient Japanese think of the traditional arts and the phenomenon. The reflexive thematisation of this Budo as methods of improving people’s physi- awareness of the phenomenon originally experienced firsthand must, according to the goal of Husserlian phe- cal skill and personalities’ [25, p. 47]. This idea is nomenology, aim at an essential description of this. certainly correct but is not restricted to Japanese

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 371 Original Article

budo. Any martial art is a method that comprises opponent does not necessarily require reaching these qualities. Considering ‘internal’ as referring the perfection of the individual (...), nor abso- to morals, mind, or spirit, and ‘external’ as refer- lute excellence (...), but only relative excellence ring to physical strength or skills, ‘Wushu (also (enough to win this particular contest)’ (p. 13). called kung fu in English) is traditional Chinese Raimondo [76] presents a similar argument: martial arts that cultivate a practitioner’s inter- ‘the richness of the philosophy underlying their nal and external qualities and abilities’ [77, p. 38]. practice would suffer too much to find breathing As suggested by these examples, particular cul- only through sports competition and, differently, tural definitions of martial arts (beyond some of maintaining a solid value-oriented to personal its singular qualities) usually express its general self-elevation is more serenely prosecuted with- features, universal facets that are shown by the out competitive concerns’ (p.45). We can refer to phenomenological reductions operating therein. this kind of transformation and polemics, which are typical between practitioners, as existential Moreover, while it is impossible to conceive of a tensions in martial arts. combat system that does not comprise an ethical (spiritual) dimension, not all combat systems are Therefore, according to the perspective adopted martial arts, especially if their typological mea- here, the assumption of Barczyński et al. ‘that sures are too restrictive, insufficiently articu- each combat sport is a martial art’ [72, p. 117] lated, or only instrumental. This can be the case can be withdrawn. Every form of martial arts is in some sporting versions, in which moral norms a cultural product that is shared and transmis- are restricted to the competitive rules or military sible. If a certain combat ethos is too particula- practices through which the ethical discernment rised or unique to a fighter, it is doubtful that it can be fulfilled one side by hierarchical obedi- is a martial art form at all. Many combat systems ence, and combative knowledge can be fulfilled originating in warrior societies have not with- by mere techniques on the other. When a martial stood the proverbial ‘test of time’, but some have art acquires a sportive version, it is possible for retained and developed both their aesthetic and it to lose consistency in such a way that it loses ethical dimensions by incorporating into them its features, both motor (esthetical) and attitudi- changes that have occurred in their respective nal (ethical). The reasons for this are suggested societies. The latter case is true for the Japanese by Lu, who says that judo and ‘were form of karate [78] and Brazilian capoeira [29], accepted by the Olympics by changing them- for instance. selves significantly, thereby losing their philo- sophical essences of Buddhism, Daoism, and The application of this line of phenomenologi- Confucianism’ [77, p.38]. In addition to the fact cal reasoning to corporal fighting opens up fields the fact that in the competitive system ‘rules of technical research that deal with aspects of a significantly restrain technique and fundamen- martial arts system, as well as fields that deal with tally distort traditional wushu’ [77, p.38], in sport, the historical, cultural, and philosophical aspects ‘seeking champions and winning medals becomes of martial arts, allowing us to discover how their the primary goal of learning/practicing in athletic individual ethical dimensions emerge. wushu, pursuing Olympic ideals such as higher, faster, and stronger’ [77, p. 39], which is detached From the perspective of moral praxis, the phil- from martial arts’ ‘traditional roots – the culti- osophical investigation has consequences with vation of fitness, self-development, and self- regard to fighting and martial arts instructors, ref- defence [77, p. 39]. Lu also argues that y, these erees, and sports institutions, as well as opinion athletic wushu performers nowadays would not makers, sports announcers, commentators, and be able to use wushu ‒ one of the most power- journalists, not forgetting, of course, the fighters ful self-defence arts ‒ to defend themselves in themselves. Such consequences are essentially real fight situations as they have not learned the related to the aforementioned proximity between proper techniques’ [77, p. 39]. physical fighting and violence. Once enlightened on the nature of corporal fighting, deviation from By the same reasoning, Martinkóvá and Parry the criteria of corporal fighting in the behav- [3, p. 13] considerer that ‘in present society the iour and motivation of fighters can be detected. emphasis on victory is immense, and often dom- We can establish that the ethical zeal in corpo- inates contemporary sport’, an approach that ral fighting is the zeal for the physical and moral ‘affects the way of fighting – victory over an integrity of practitioners. Thus, in a fight, when

372 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

the physical limits of one of the fighters is over- of corporal fighting. The fighting spirit contains an stepped, that is, each time physical aggression ethical essence that can counter violence and is reaches an intensity that is no longer acceptable ultimately opposed to its promotion. The fact to one partner and the fight is not interrupted, that Mars is considered virtuous, as opposed the criterion of mutual availability can be deemed to the disruptive and impulsive Ares, leads us, to have been injured, trespassing beyond the through this cultural expression, toward its essen- frontier of corporal fighting and into the territory tial manifestation. Precisely, the ethical essence of violence. The fighter displaying such aggres- expressed by Mars virtuosity allows staying in sion must halt it when the limit is exceeded. In communication about identical, even if neces- the context of teaching fighting, one of the cen- sarily differentiating, phenomena. tral roles of the instructor is to ensure that this limit is not reached, while in the sporting context This paper attempts to contribute to the issues the central role of the referee and the regulatory on the intentional lived structure of these phe- institution is to maintain this limit. Crossing these nomena, but not without considering its lim- boundaries, however, may mutilate the essence itations The first is related to the difficulty of of the challenge of corporal fighting, preventing understanding phenomenology, a living philos- the self-development of a martial artist. ophy that, since its beginning, has witnessed important philosophical disputes about its way In addition, the present study is explicit regarding of being applied and its pretentions. To prop- the inherent characteristics of martial arts that erly use definitions that have been reached phe- provide the conditions for an existential answer nomenologically means to understand the need to the problems that prevail in contemporary to grasp intentions, the intentionality of actions. society [34]. They provide a meaningful expe- Therefore, boxing can be grasped as a martial art, rience that help practitioners face life [38] and but not objectively from the natural orientation form close family bonds [35]; they also constitute sin.ce from this pre-conceptual point of view, a corporal practice in which states of conscious- boxing is seen just as a sport. As we argued in ness are reached through experiences of a reli- the initial paragraphs of this paper, some forms gious nature undergone in practice [22]. This is of combat sports, such as boxing and wrestling, a subjective process that has been addressed by which are not necessarily related to the cultural the field of anthropology of the body [65]. Martial notions of martial arts, must be shown by put- arts also provides a training program, by way of ting in brackets the factual, cultural, particular- decisive lived experiences, that turns a life into ised, and objectified view of what martial arts is: a work of art [37], and, as Figueiredo [41] states, it can be grasped as martial arts whilst lived as potentially contribute to the determination of the martial arts in a communitarian context. Even if objects of scientific studies. he does not claim this classification for boxing, Wacquant [79] describes how, from the point of Only the articulated values and motivations view of its practitioners, boxing is about teach- for lived experiences determining combative ing discipline and self-respect as well self-de- practices make possible to penetrate in what, fence and violence. This comprehension unifies effectively, pushes the so-called psycho-so- the double feature of the object (MA) and the cial outcomes of martial arts practice. It also subject (practitioner) and looks for a comparison concerns the self-regulation of the athlete in a between concept and case/situation grounded combat sport, as the specific interests of sports on lived experiences (intentionality). Another psychology. Research that does not consider limitation is that analyses are always subjected these interests will necessarily establish portraits to new re-descriptions, which seise other facets of correlations that are just circumstantial; that and specificities, deepening and making more is, ‘contrasting finds’ [5, p. 200] will be produced precise the differentiation between lived expe- about the relationship between combative prac- riences. This is shown by the range of analyses tices and anti-social behaviour, without any solid that for some years now [80-82] have allowed of basis for obtaining results using the universal sci- a gradual deepening of the differences between entific scope intended by science. lived experiences, which is now being presented in a manner that is believed to be global and None of the preceding information can be com- satisfactory. prehended without explicitly establishing how martial arts results from the intentional structure

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 373 Original Article

CONCLUSIONS of combative experiences, especially corporal In conclusion, we paraphrase Polish philosopher fighting, is a banal thing: ‘But, despite being banal, Roman Ingarden, concerning his findings about none of the authors I knew has clearly seen that the literary work of art, and say that the phe- here lie the fundamental structures that conform nomenological approach of martial arts presented to the essence’ [68, p. 87] of fighting and martial here, by making patent the intentional structure arts experiences.

REFERENCES

1. Kalina RM, Barczyński BJ. Editorial: Prestige 15. Nesti, MS. Phenomenology and sport psy- Franchini E, Del Vechio FB, editors. Ensino de and impact archives of Budo for scientific chology: Back to the things themselves. Sport, Lutas: Reflexões e Propostas de Programas. São research of the martial arts. Arch Budo 2010; Ethics and Phil 2011; 5: 285-296 Paulo: Scortecci; 2012: 62-73 [in Portuguese] 6(1): 53-55 16. Halák J, Jirásek I, Nesti MS. Phenomenology 30. McCarthy P. The bible of karate: Bubishi. 2. Pérez-Gutiérrez M, Gutiérrez-García C, is not phenomenalism. Is there such a thing McCarthy P, translator and commentator. Escobar-Molina R. Terminological recom- as phenomenology of sport? Acta Gymnica Boston: Tuttle; 1995 mendations for improving the visibility of 2014; 44(2): 117-129 scientific literature on martial arts and com- 31. Donohue J, Taylor, K. The classification of the bat sports. Arch Budo 2011; 7(3): 159-166 17. Ales Bello A. Phenomenological hyletics and fighting arts. J Asian Mart Arts 1994; 3(4): the lifeworld. Analecta Husserliana 2005; 10-37 3. Martínková I, Parry J. Martial categories: clar- LXXXIV: 293-301 ification and classification. J Phil Sport 2015; 32. Theeboom M, De Knop P, Vertonghen J. 43(1): 1-20 18. Ales Bello A. Il senso del sacro: dall’arcaicità Experiences of children in martial arts. Euro alla desacralizzazione. Roma: Castelvecchi; J Sport and Societ 2009; 6(1): 19-35 4. Klimczak J, Podstawski R, Dobosz D. The asso- 2014 [in Italian] ciation of sport and violence, aggression and 33. Kavoura A, Ryba TV, Kokkonen M. Psychological aggressiveness – prospects for education about 19. Husserl E. Ideas: General introduction to research on martial artists: A critical view from nonaggression and reduction of aggressive- pure phenomenology. London and New York: a cultural praxis framework. Scand Sport Stud ness. Arch Budo 2014; 10: 273-286 Routledge Taylor & Francis Group; 2002 Forum 2012; 3: 1-23 5. Theeboom M. A closer look at effects of mar- 20. Vey G. Integrative combat: An empirical per- 34. Looser D. The risk society and martial arts tial arts involvement among youth. Int J Sport spective of the martial arts. J Asian Mart Arts training in New Zealand. J Asian Mart Arts Manag and Market. 2012; 11(3/4): 193-205 2010; 19(2): 8-21 2006; 15(1): 8-23 6. Fahlberg LL, Fahlberg LA, Gates WK. Exercise 21. Habersetzer G, Habersetzer R. Encyclopedie 35. Lantz J. Family development and the martial and existence: exercise behavior from an exis- des arts martiaux de l’extreme Orient: tech- arts: A phenomenological study. Contemp Fam tential-phenomenological perspective. Sport nique, historique, biographique et culturelle. Ther 2002; 24(4): 565-580 Saint-Nabor: Ed. Amphora; 2000 [in French] Psychol 1992; 6: 172-191 36. Lu C. Eastern martial arts and violence pre- 7. Fahlberg LL, Fahlberg LA. A human science 22. Keenan JP. Spontaneity in Western Martial vention: Reversing a stereotype. Arch Budo for the study of movement: an integration of Arts – A Yogocara critique of mushin (no- 2008; 4: 32-36 mind). Jpn J Relig Stud 1989; 16(4): 285-298 multiple ways of knowing. Res Q Exerc Sport 37. Monahan M. The practice of self-overcoming: 1994; 64(2): 100-109 23. Braunstein F. Penser les arts martiaux. Paris: Nietzschean reflections on the martial arts. J 8. Kerry DS, Armour KM. Sport science and Presses Universitaires de France; 1999 [in French] Phil of Sport 2007; 34: 39-51 the promise of phenomenology: Philosophy, 24. Kalina RM, Barczyński, BJ. Archives of Budo – 38. Columbus PJ, Rice D. Phenomenological mean- method, and insight. Quest 2000; 52: 1-17 dialogue about the personal safety and action ings of martial arts participation. J Sport Behav 9. Nicholls AR, Holt NL, Polman RC. A phenom- worth the man. Arch Budo 2008; 4: 1-3 1998; 21(1): 16-29 enological analysis of coping effectiveness in 25. Sasaki T. Budo (the martial arts) as Japanese 39. Cynarski WJ. Teoria i praktyka dalekowschod- golf. Sport Psychol 2005; 19: 111-130 culture. The outlook on the techniques and nich sztuk walki w perspektywie europejskiej, 10. Hogenová, A. Movement and time. Acta the outlook on the human being. Arch Budo Rzeszow: Rzeszow University Press; 2004 cited Universitatis Palackianae Olomucensis. 2008; 4: 46-49 (and translated) in Cynarski WJ, Kudlacz M. Gymnica 2006; 36(2): 47-51 Injuries in martial arts and combat sports – a 26. Anglo S. The martial arts of renaissance Europe. comparative study. Arch Budo 2008; 4: 82-88 11. Martínková I. Jan Patočka’s three movements New Haven and London: Yale University Press; of human life with respect to physical edu- 2000 40. Correia WR, Franchini E. Produção acadêmica cation and sport practice. Acta Universitatis em lutas, artes marciais e esportes de com- 27. Dervenis K, Lykiardopoulos N. The martial bate. Motriz 2010; 16 (1): 1-9 [in Portuguese] Palackianae Olomucensis. Gymnica 2006; arts of Ancient Greece: Modern fighting tech- 36(2): 59-66 niques from the age of Alexanders. Rochester: 41. Figueiredo A. The object of study in martial arts 12. Vannatta S. A phenomenology of sport: Playing Destiny Books; 2007 and combat sports research – Contributions to a complex whole. In: Cynarski W, editor. and passive synthesis. J Phil Sport 2008; 35: 28. Cognot F. Histoires et éthiques: visions et 63-72 Martial Arts and Combat Sports – Humanistic images des problématiques d’éthique dans Outlook. Rzeszów: Wydawnictwo Uniwersytetu 13. Allen-Collinson J, Sporting embodiment: sports les arts martiaux de l’Europe médiévale et Rzeszowskiego; 2009: 20-34 studies and the (continuing) promise of phe- moderne. In: Heuser F, Touboul A, Terrisse nomenology. Q Res Sport and Exerc 2009; A, editors. Ethique, Sport de Combat & Arts 42. Reid H, Croucher M. The fighting arts. New 1(3): 279-296 Martiaux. Toulouse: Presses de l´Université de York: Simon and Schuster; 1983 Toulose 1 Capitole; 2013: 81-93 [in French] 14. Martínková I, Parry J. Two ways of conceiving 43. Poliakof MB. Combat sports in the ancient time in sports. Acta Universitatis Palackianae 29. Valério PHM, Barreira CRA. A cultura capoeira world: competition, violence, and culture. New Olomucensis. Gymnica 2011; 41(1): 23-31 como fonte pedagógica da prática capoeira. In: Haven and London: Yale University Press; 1987

374 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com Barreira CRA. – The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting...

44. Sánchez García R, Malcolm D. Decivilizing, psychomotor adaptation – a key factor in teach- 78. Barreira CRA, Massimi M. O combate sub- civilizing or informalizing? The international ing self-defence. Arch Budo 2005; 1(1): 19-26 trativo: a espiritualidade do esvaziamento development of . Int Rev como norte da filosofia corporal no Karate-Do. Sociol Sport 2010; 45(39): 39-58 61. Weitlauf, JC, Smith RE, Cervone D. Psicologia: Reflexão e Crítica 2008; 21(2): 283- Generalizations effects of coping-skills training: 292 [in Portuguese] 45. Priest G, Young D, editors. Philosophy and the Influence of self-defense training on women’s martial arts. London: Routledge; 2014 efficacy beliefs, assertiveness, and aggression. 79. Wacquant L. The pugilistic point of view: How J Appl Psychol 2000; 85(4): 625-633 boxers think and feel about their trade. Theory 46. Terrisse, A. Pour un enseignement dialectique and Society 1995; 24: 489-535 des sport de combat. Revue EPS 1991; 229: 62. Brecklin LR, Ullman SE. Self-defense or asser- 23-26 [in French] tiveness training and women’s responses to 80. Barreira CRA. Uma análise fenomenológica da sexual attacks. J IP Viol 2005; 20(6): 738-762 luta corporal e da arte marcial. In: Proceedings 47. Avelar B, Figueiredo A. La iniciación a los of the 4th Seminário Internacional de Pesquisa deportes de combate: interpretación de la 63. Cazalbou P. La légitime defense appliquée aux e Estudos Qualitativos (SIPEQ); 2010 Oct 9-11; estructura del fenómeno lúdico luctatorio. sports de combat et arts martiaux. In: Heuser Rio Claro, Brazil [in Portuguese] Rev de Artes Marciales Asiáticas 2009; 4(3): F, Touboul A, Terrisse A, editors. Ethique, Sport 44-57 [in Spanish] de Combat & Arts Martiaux. Toulouse: Presses 81. Barreira CRA. Fenomenologia do combate: de l´Université de Toulose 1 Capitole; 2013: da ética da luta à luta pela vida ética. In: 48. Gomes M, Morato M, Duarte E et al. 21-35 [in French] Mahfoud M, Massimi M, editors. Edith Stein e Ensino das Lutas: dos princípios condicio- a Psicologia: Teoria e Pesquisa. Belo Horizonte: nais aos grupos situacionais. Movimento 64. Broomé RE. An empathetic psychological ArteSã; 2013: 413-447 [in Portuguese] 2010; 16(2): 207‐227 [in Portuguese] perspective of police deadly force training. J Phenom Psychol 2011; 42(2): 137-156 82. Barreira CRA. L´essence du combat: une 49. Avelar-Rosa B, Figueiredo A. As Artes Marciais approche phénoménologique des arts mar- e Desportos de Combate na Educação 65. Bizerril J. Aesthetics of existence in flow: Taoist tiaux et sports de combat dans sa dimension Física Escolar – Interpretação Curricular. J corporeity and the contemporary world. Soc éthique. In: Heuser F, Touboul A, Terrisse, A, Sport Pedag and Res 2015; 1(8): 14-21 [in Sci Relig 2011; 12(13): 77-101 editors. Ethique, Sport de Combat & Arts Portuguese] 66. Stein E. Una ricerca sullo stato. Ales Bello A, Martiaux. Toulouse: Presses de l´Université de 50. Avelar-Rosa B, Gomes MSP, Figueiredo A translator. Roma: Città Nuova; 1999 [in Italian] Toulose Capitole; 2013: 277-292 [in French] et al. Caracterización y desarrollo del “saber 83. Kotarbiński T. Z zagadnień ogólnej teorii walki luchar”: contenidos de un modelo integrado 67. Reinach A. I fondamenti a priori del diritto civile. Milano: Giuffrè; 1990 [in Italian] [From Problems of General Theory of Struggle]. para la enseñanza de las artes marciales y de los Warszawa: Sekcja Psychologiczna Towarzystwa deportes de combate. Rev de Artes Marciales 68. Ingarden, R. L’opera d’arte letteraria. Gasperoni Wiedzy Wojskowej; 1938 [in Polish] Asiáticas 2015; 10(1): 16-33 [in Spanish] L, translator. Verona: Fondazione Centro Studi Campostrini; 2011 [in Italian] 84. Konieczny J. Cybernetyka walki [A Cybernetic of 51. Ales Bello A. The language of our living body. Struggle]. Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Analecta Husserliana 2006; LXXXIV: 293-301 69. Pezzella AM. Lineamenti di filosofia Naukowe. 1970 [in Polish, summary in English 52. Husserl E. Natural scientific psychology, human dell’educazione: per una prospettiva fenom- and Russian] enológica dell’evento educativo. Città del sciences and metaphysics (1919). In: Nenon 85. Rudniański J. Elementy prakseologicznej teo- T, Embree L, editors. Issues in Husserl’s Ideas Vaticano: Lateran university Press; 2007 [in Italian] rii walki. Z zagadnień kooperacji negatywnej II. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers; [Elements of Praxiological Theory of Struggle. From 1996: 8-13 70. Stein E. On the problem of empathy. 3rd ed. Problems of a Negative Co-operation]. Warszawa: 53. Appiah KA. The honor code: how moral rev- Washington: ICS Publication; 1989 Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. 1983 [in Polish] olutions happen. London: W.W. Norton & 71. Ales Bello A. From empathy to solidarity: inter- Company; 2010 subjective connections according to Edith Stein. 86. Rudniański J. Kompromis i walka. Sprawność 54. Zahavi D. Subjectivity and selfhood: Analecta Husserliana 1996; XLVIII: 367-375 i etyka kooperacji pozytywnej i negaty- wnej w gęstym otoczeniu społecznym [A Investigating the first-person perspective. 72. Barczyńskil BJ, Graczyński MR, Kalina RM. Compromise and a Struggle. The Efficiency and Cambridge (MA) and London: MIT Press; 2005 Budo – a unique keyword of life sciences. Ethics of Positive and Negative Co-operation in a Arch Budo 2009; 5: 117-119 55. Depraz N. Compreendre la phénoménologie: Dense Social Environment]. Warszawa: Instytut uma pratique concrète. Paris: Armand Colin; 73. Krzemieniecki LA, Kalina RM. Agon – a term Wydawniczy Pax; 1989 [in Polish] 2006 [in French] connecting the theory of struggle with belles- 87. Kalina RM. Przeciwdziałanie agresji. lettres. A perspective of inter-disciplinary 56. Depraz N. Lire Husserl en Phénoménologue. Wykorzystanie sportu do zmniejszania research. Arch Budo 2011; 7(4): 255-265 Paris: PUF; 2008 [in French] agresywności [Counteracting aggression. The use of sport to reduce aggressiveness]. Warszawa: 57. Sánchez Garcia R. Análisis etnometodológico 74. Kalina RM. Agonology as a deeply esoteric sci- Polskie Towarzystwo Higieny Psychicznej; 1991 sobre el dinamismo del habitus en Bourdieu y ence – an introduction to martial arts ther- [in Polish, summary in English] Elias dentro del desarrollo de actividades cor- apy on a global scale. Procedia Manufacturing 2015; 3: 1195-1202 porales. Revista Española de Investigaciones 88. Kalina RM: Teoria sportów walki [Theory of Sociológicas 2008; 124: 209-231 [in Spanish] 75. Barczyński BJ, Kalina RM. Science of martial Combat Sports]. Warszawa: COS; 2000 [in Polish] 58. Melo F, Barreira CRA. Psychological barri- arts – Example of the dilemma in classifying new interdisciplinary sciences in the global ers between violence, fight and game: phe- 89. Budō: The Martial Ways of Japan. Tokyo: systems of the science evaluation and the nomenological transitions in the practice of Nippon Budokan Foundation; 2009 capoeira. Movimento (ESEF/UFRGS) 2015; social consequences of courageous decisions. 21(1): 125-138 Procedia Manufacturing 2015; 3: 1203-1210 90. Dictionary of Sport and Exercise Science. Over 5,000 Terms Clearly Defined. London: 76. Raimondo S, editor. Vibrazioni nella forza: sto- 59. Del Vechio FB. Ensino de defesa pessoal na A & B Black; 2006 educação básica e no ensino superior. In: ria critica delle discipline orientali. Molfetta: Franchini E, Del Vechio FB, editors. Ensino de la Meridiana; 2007 [in Italian] 91. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Simulacra_and_ Simulation (accessed 2016 Apr 30) Lutas: Reflexões e Propostas de Programas. São 77. Lu C. Modern wushu: When Chinese mar- Paulo: Scortecci; 2012: 47-61 [in Portuguese] tial arts meet Western sports. Arch Budo 60. Harasymowicz J, Kalina RM. Training of 2008; 4: 37-39

© ARCHIVES OF BUDO | PHILOSOPHY 2017 | VOLUME 13 | 375 Original Article

Cite this article as: Barreira CRA. The essences of martial arts and corporal fighting: A classical phenomenological analysis. Arch Budo 2017; 13: 351-376

EDITORIAL NOTE This valuable article by Cristiano Roque Antunes Barreira is an example of intellectual and cognitive losses that arose as a result of the political division of the world after the Second World War – Cold War and Iron Curtain [92, 93]. The editors, taking advantage of the privilege to correct the text of the manuscript, removed (irrespective of the explanations in the glossary) the following fragment of the author’s statement: ‘None of the definitions offered in the literature for any of these cultural objects is based on phenomenological analysis; moreover, the literature offers no precise definitions that encom- pass the wide variety of practices found within these phenomena’.

Especially Jarosław Rudniański (1921-2008), who after the end of the martial law in Poland published in 1989 in Polish the fundamental work of agonology: A Compromise and a Struggle. The Efficiency and Ethics of Positive and Negative Co-operation in a Dense Social Environment [86]; makes a broad phenom- enological analysis of the concept of ‘fight’. He refers to Heraclitus from Ephesus, Thomas Hobbes, Charles Robert Darwin, Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, Bhagavadgita, David’s fight against Goliath, but also to Karl Marx’s class conflict, or to Adolf Hitler’s Mein Kampf.

The paper of Cristiano Roque Antunes Barreira, published in the Archives of Budo, is valuable for at least two reasons. First, it reinforces the argumentation emphasizing the cognitive (scientific) and social consequences of isolating knowledge about struggle as a result of ideological and political divisions [74, 92-94] – language barriers [83-88] are a secondary consequence. Second, it supple- ments the basic knowledge about fight in the context of the growing martial arts bibliotherapy in global science space [73, 95, 96].

RECOMMENDED REFERENCES

92. Barczyński BJ, Graczyński M, Kalina RM. Barriers Restricting the Free Dissemination of Scientific Achievements: Own Experiences in Crossing Walls and Bridges J Hum Kinet 2009; 22(22): 7-14 93. Kalina RM. Cognitive and application barriers to the use of “Agonology in Preventive and Therapeutic dimension”. In: Salmon P, Macquet AC, editors. Advances in Human Factors in Sports and Outdoor Recreation. Proceedings of the HFE 2016 International Conference on Human Factors in Sports and Outdoor Recreation, July 27-31, 2016, Walt Disney World®, Florida, USA Series: Advances in Intelligent Systems and Computing 2016; 496: 25-35 94. Kalina RM. Agonology – the unknown science. Arch Budo 2016; 12: 231-237 95. Klimczak J, Krzemieniecki LA, Mosler D. Martial arts bibliotherapy – the possibility of compensating the negative effects of the continuous education for aggression by electronic media and the aggressive interpersonal relation- ship of children and adults. Arch Budo 2015; 11: 395-340 96. Krzemieniecki LA, Moska W. Combat issues in literary works of Nobel Laureates for Literature – an interdisciplinary perspective of martial arts bibliotherapy. Arch Budo 2016; 12: 345-352

376 | VOLUME 13 | 2017 www.archbudo.com