TOWARD CLASSICAL LEGAL POSITIVISM Dan Priel* I. THE

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

TOWARD CLASSICAL LEGAL POSITIVISM Dan Priel* I. THE PRIEL_BOOK (DO NOT DELETE) 5/14/2015 3:22 PM TOWARD CLASSICAL LEGAL POSITIVISM Dan Priel* I. THE ROAD NOT TAKEN HEN H.L.A. Hart defended legal positivism in his famous W Holmes Lecture, he sought to do so “as part of the history of an idea.”1 In his hands this idea grew out of two philosophical traditions. One of them was utilitarianism, the belief that the moral assessment of states of affairs must be based on their contribution to happiness, while the other was “the important truth that a purely analytical study of legal concepts, a study of the meaning of the distinctive vocabulary of the law, was as vital to our understanding of the nature of law as historical or sociological studies.”2 Together these two ideas led to a “simple but vital distinction” between “law as it is [and] law as it ought to be.”3 It is not difficult to see that the two ideas Hart talked about are in ten- sion: Bentham, to whom Hart ascribes both, conceived of his utilitarian- ism as part of an attempt to ground the domain of morals and politics on the same foundations and conducted with the same rigor as the natural sciences. His empiricism implied that the principles of morals and legis- lation had to be based on observation, not conceptual or linguistic analy- sis. It is true that he dedicated many pages to the analysis of language, but this work was concerned not with the analytical study of concepts, but with exposing the extent to which language obscured reality. Legal language in particular came under relentless attack, because Bentham found it riddled with so many fictions, ambiguities, and absurdities. As such, it stood in the way of a clear description of reality and was an ob- stacle to the betterment of the human condition. As Bentham caustically put it, “[a] large portion of the body of the Law was, by the bigotry or * Associate Professor, Osgoode Hall Law School. I thank participants in the symposium at the University of Virginia for their comments, and especially to Jeff Pojanowski for his commentary on the version presented at the symposium. Earlier versions of this Article were presented at the annual conference of the Australian Society of Legal Philosophy and Queen Mary, the University of London. I thank participants there for their questions and comments. I also thank Charles Barzun and Lucas Miotto for their written comments on earlier drafts. 1 H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 593, 594 (1958). 2 Id. at 601. 3 Id. at 594. 987 PRIEL_BOOK (DO NOT DELETE) 5/14/2015 3:22 PM 988 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 101:987 the artifice of Lawyers, locked up in an illegible character, and in a for- eign tongue.”4 For him, the only path for true understanding of the law came not from paying attention to the thick foliage of legal discourse but rather by cutting through it.5 Once we see that utilitarianism and linguistic analysis of the kind Hart championed are not natural bedfellows, we can turn Hart’s claim on its head: The history of jurisprudence reveals two distinct versions of legal positivism which are not easily joined. And indeed, it did not take long for Hart himself to abandon the link between utilitarianism and legal positivism. Perhaps he no longer thought it necessary to draw such a strong link between the two when no longer facing an audience he sus- pected would be unsympathetic to conceptual inquiry;6 or perhaps Hart simply came to recognize the two are quite different.7 Be that as it may, by the time The Concept of Law was published, only four years after de- livering the Lecture, legal positivism’s utilitarian connection was largely gone. It was still presented as a simple idea that (unlike natural law) did not require taking on “much metaphysics, which few could now ac- cept,”8 but it was now much more the result of conceptual analysis and 4 Jeremy Bentham, A Fragment on Government 21 n.r (J.H. Burns & H.L.A. Hart eds., 1988) (1776). The fictional nature of legal language was a major theme in Bentham’s work. He often accused lawyers of keeping legal language complex for self-serving reasons. See Philip Schofield, Utility and Democracy: The Political Thought of Jeremy Bentham 114–31 (2006). 5 I am less concerned in this Article with the other figure to whom Hart ascribes these views, John Austin. Austin’s interests were more different than Bentham’s than is usually appreciated. See John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined 26–27 (Wilfrid E. Rumble ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1995) (1832). For more on the difference between Aus- tin and Hart, see Dan Priel, H.L.A. Hart and the Invention of Legal Philosophy, 5 Problema 301, 311–16 (2011). Austin clearly was interested in getting one’s language right, but for all his pedantry over law “properly so called,” Austin did not see himself as concerned with elu- cidating prevalent linguistic usage and he rejected it when it did not fit into his scheme. 6 On Hart’s comments on the difference between his approach and that of the Harvard pro- fessors and his worries about the reception of his lecture, see Nicola Lacey, A Life of H.L.A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream 195–96 (2004). 7 See his somewhat different characterization of Bentham’s enterprise in H.L.A. Hart, Essays on Bentham: Studies in Jurisprudence and Political Theory 21–39 (1982); cf. P.S. Atiyah & Robert S. Summers, Form and Substance in Anglo-American Law: A Comparative Study of Legal Reasoning, Legal Theory, and Legal Institutions 256 (1987) (“[U]tilitarianism all but dropped out of English legal theory in the latter part of the nineteenth century, and instrumen- talism never did have much place in English positivism.”). 8 H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law 188 (Penelope A. Bulloch & Joseph Raz eds., 3d ed. 2012). PRIEL_BOOK (DO NOT DELETE) 5/14/2015 3:22 PM 2015] Toward Classical Legal Positivism 989 armchair sociology9 than the conclusion of any ethical or metaethical in- quiry. Decades later, when Hart wrote the postscript to The Concept of Law, he said: “I still think legal theory should avoid commitment to con- troversial philosophical theories of the general status of moral judgments and should leave open . the general question of whether they have . ‘objective standing.’”10 In other words, one reason to favor his linguistic approach to legal philosophy was precisely that it was not connected to a particular moral theory. Knowing Hart’s personal doubts on questions relating to the foundations of morality,11 it is likely part of the attraction that conceptual legal positivism held for him lay in the fact that it allowed him to remain agnostic on questions about which he was personally conflicted. One of the marks of the extraordinary influence of The Concept of Law is that most defenses of legal positivism in the last fifty years have adopted this conceptualist approach. From here it was but a small step to the startling claim made by John Gardner, that even in the case of Ben- tham himself his utilitarianism and his legal positivism were completely separable: Bentham’s preference for legislation over the common law— a view that was closely tied to his utilitarianism—is “totally independent of his legal positivism.”12 Legal positivism was thus stripped by most of its contemporary proponents of the particular historical context in which it appeared, of its links to the Enlightenment, of the many ways in which its (alleged) earlier proponents tied it to their political thought, and turned into a proposition. It was defended as a conceptual truth about the “nature” of law, the result of nothing more than careful attention to the “study of the meaning of the distinctive vocabulary of the law.”13 For this proposition to count as a philosophical thesis, not merely an incontestable, observational truism, there was a need for a contender. And a contender was duly found; or, more accurately, invented. It was called “natural law.” Of course, natural law is a philosophical tradition with a provenance stretching back to earliest recorded Western philoso- 9 How these two seemingly different projects connect in Hart is explained in Dan Priel, Jurisprudence Between Science and the Humanities, 4 Wash. U. Juris. Rev. 269, 303–04 (2012). 10 Hart, supra note 8, at 253–54. 11 See Neil MacCormick, H.L.A. Hart 207 (2d ed. 2008). 12 John Gardner, Law as a Leap of Faith: Essays on Law in General 36–37 (2012). In ra- ther similar fashion Hart complained that “at some important points [Bentham’s] utilitarian- ism gets in the way of his analytical vision.” Hart, supra note 7, at 162. 13 Hart, supra note 1, at 601. PRIEL_BOOK (DO NOT DELETE) 5/14/2015 3:22 PM 990 Virginia Law Review [Vol. 101:987 phy, but this historical, natural law is, as Peter Gay once put it, “infinite- ly complex; to draw a map of its growth, its multiple ingredients, its changing modes and varied influence, would be like drawing a map of the Nile Delta.”14 In this vast river one finds discussions on the founda- tions of political authority, the limits of political obligation, the origins of property rights, the justification of contractual obligations, the per- missibility of capital punishment, along with much else. Little of this was acknowledged in the work of Hart or his followers.
Recommended publications
  • Legal Positivism: an Analysis of Austin and Bentham
    INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 LEGAL POSITIVISM: AN ANALYSIS OF AUSTIN AND BENTHAM Authors PRAGALBH BHARDWAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] RISHI RAJ National Law University, Odisha BH-1, National Law University, Odisha, Sector 13, CDA, Cuttack, Odisha. Country-India [email protected] 1 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF LAW AND LEGAL JURISPRUDENCE STUDIES, VOLUME 1, ISSUE 6 Abstract Key words- Austin, Bentham, Criticism of Positivist School, Indian Perspective of Positivist School, Legal Positivist School. The school of Legal Positivism developed over the period of 18th and 19th century through the works of influential jurists such as John Austin and Jeremey Bentham. The works of these two great jurists was mainly responsible for the Legal Positivist School to acquire such importance in the field of legal jurisprudence. Their work was taken forward by jurists such as H.L.A.Hart. Although not free from shortcomings, the Legal Positivist School is regarded as the most influential school of thought in jurisprudence. Judges have based their decisions on this school of thought across various countries, including India. Indian Judges have been greatly influenced by the thinking of legal positivists and have applied their jurisprudence while giving landmark judgements such as A.K.Gopalan v. State of Madras to name one of them. The basic idea behind legal positivists was that they considered law as it is and not what it ought to be. They separated moral principles from legal principles.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Samuele Chilovi
    Legal Theory Workshop UCLA School of Law Samuele Chilovi Postdoctoral Fellow Pompeu Fabra University “GROUNDING, EXPLANATION, AND LEGAL POSITIVISM” Thursday, October 15, 2020, 12:15-1:15 pm Via Zoom Draft, October 6, 2020. For UCLA Workshop. Please Don’t Cite Or Quote Without Permission. Grounding, Explanation, and Legal Positivism Samuele Chilovi & George Pavlakos 1. Introduction On recent prominent accounts, legal positivism and physicalism about the mind are viewed as making parallel claims about the metaphysical determinants or grounds of legal and mental facts respectively.1 On a first approximation, while physicalists claim that facts about consciousness, and mental phenomena more generally, are fully grounded in physical facts, positivists similarly maintain that facts about the content of the law (in a legal system, at a time) are fully grounded in descriptive social facts.2 Explanatory gap arguments have long played a central role in evaluating physicalist theories in the philosophy of mind, and as such have been widely discussed in the literature.3 Arguments of this kind typically move from a claim that an epistemic gap between physical and phenomenal facts implies a corresponding metaphysical gap, together with the claim that there is an epistemic gap between facts of these kinds, to the negation of physicalism. Such is the structure of, for instance, Chalmers’ (1996) conceivability argument, Levine’s (1983) intelligibility argument, and Jackson’s (1986) knowledge argument. Though less prominently than in the philosophy of mind, explanatory gap arguments have also played some role in legal philosophy. In this area, the most incisive and compelling use of an argument of this kind is constituted by Greenberg’s (2004, 2006a, 2006b) powerful attack on positivism.
    [Show full text]
  • Positivism and the Inseparability of Law and Morals
    \\server05\productn\N\NYU\83-4\NYU403.txt unknown Seq: 1 25-SEP-08 12:20 POSITIVISM AND THE INSEPARABILITY OF LAW AND MORALS LESLIE GREEN* H.L.A. Hart made a famous claim that legal positivism somehow involves a “sepa- ration of law and morals.” This Article seeks to clarify and assess this claim, con- tending that Hart’s separability thesis should not be confused with the social thesis, the sources thesis, or a methodological thesis about jurisprudence. In contrast, Hart’s separability thesis denies the existence of any necessary conceptual connec- tions between law and morality. That thesis, however, is false: There are many necessary connections between law and morality, some of them conceptually signif- icant. Among them is an important negative connection: Law is, of its nature, morally fallible and morally risky. Lon Fuller emphasized what he called the “internal morality of law,” the “morality that makes law possible.” This Article argues that Hart’s most important message is that there is also an immorality that law makes possible. Law’s nature is seen not only in its internal virtues, in legality, but also in its internal vices, in legalism. INTRODUCTION H.L.A. Hart’s Holmes Lecture gave new expression to the old idea that legal systems comprise positive law only, a thesis usually labeled “legal positivism.” Hart did this in two ways. First, he disen- tangled the idea from the independent and distracting projects of the imperative theory of law, the analytic study of legal language, and non-cognitivist moral philosophies. Hart’s second move was to offer a fresh characterization of the thesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards Classical Legal Positivism Dan Priel Osgoode Hall Law School of York University, [email protected]
    Osgoode Hall Law School of York University Osgoode Digital Commons Research Papers, Working Papers, Conference Comparative Research in Law & Political Economy Papers Research Report No. 20/2011 Towards Classical Legal Positivism Dan Priel Osgoode Hall Law School of York University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/clpe Recommended Citation Priel, Dan, "Towards Classical Legal Positivism" (2011). Comparative Research in Law & Political Economy. Research Paper No. 20/2011. http://digitalcommons.osgoode.yorku.ca/clpe/58 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Research Papers, Working Papers, Conference Papers at Osgoode Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Comparative Research in Law & Political Economy by an authorized administrator of Osgoode Digital Commons. ! ! ! !"#!!$%!&'(()('*)"+&!!(! !"#$%&%'()*+,*-*%&./+(0+1%2+3+4"5('(.%5+6."0"#7+ ) ,%"%',+&)-'-%,)"%,.%") "#$#%&'(!)%*#&!+,-!.00.122! Towards Classical Legal Positivism! Dan Priel ) ) IC65,&$:) -556)789:30450);!4<==15)&3>>)(3?)"@A==>B)C=6=0D=B)$/65@D=6)+=9E363D/F5)) ,54536@A)/0)(3?)301)-=>/D/@3>)%@=0=92G) H=A0)*I)+/=JJ/);K0/F564/D2)=J)+3>/J=60/3)3D),/F564/15G) (553005)L==D930);!4<==15)&3>>)(3?)"@A==>B)C=6=0D=B)-6=18@D/=0)%1/D=6G) ! ! ! ! ! ! Towards Classical Legal Positivism Dan Priel* Abstract. Open almost any textbook or jurisprudence and you will nd it beginning with a discussion of natural law and legal positivism. What sets them apart, we are told, is a di"erence on the conceptual question of the relationship between law and morality. Natural lawyers believe that law or legality are necessarily connected to morality, whereas legal positivists deny that.
    [Show full text]
  • Demanding Philosophy from Legal Positivism: an Investigation Into the Argumentative Support for the Separation Thesis
    Demanding Philosophy from Legal Positivism: An Investigation into the Argumentative Support for the Separation Thesis by Samuel Steadman A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral affairs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of M.A. Legal Studies Carleton University Ottawa, Ontario ©2011 Samuel Steadman Library and Archives Bibliotheque et 1*1 Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de I'edition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington OttawaONK1A0N4 OttawaONK1A0N4 Canada Canada Your We Votre inference ISBN: 978-0-494-81624-0 Our file Notre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-81624-0 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accorde une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library and permettant a la Bibliotheque et Archives Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduire, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par telecommunication ou par I'lnternet, preter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des theses partout dans le loan, distribute and sell theses monde, a des fins commerciales ou autres, sur worldwide, for commercial or non­ support microforme, papier, electronique et/ou commercial purposes, in microform, autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriete du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in this et des droits moraux qui protege cette these. Ni thesis. Neither the thesis nor la these ni des extraits substantiels de celle-ci substantial extracts from it may be ne doivent etre im primes ou autrement printed or otherwise reproduced reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Law As a Means
    LEGAL RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Paper No 8/2009 March 2009 Law as a Means LESLIE GREEN A revised version of this paper will appear in Peter Cane, ed. Hart-Fuller at 50 (Oxford: Hart Publishing) An abstract of this paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network electronic library at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1351304 An index to the working papers in the University of Oxford Legal Research Paper Series is located at: <http://www.ssrn.com/link/oxford-legal-studies.html> LAW AS A MEANS Leslie Green∗ I. The instrumentalist thesis No one doubts that individual laws often serve as means to promote or secure certain ends. The rule against perpetuities is a means of setting temporal limitations on the grant of an estate. Bundles of laws working through statutes or fields of doctrine are also means to ends, including ends that are, under other descriptions, means to further ends. Enacting the Fewer School Boards Act1, for example, was intended as a means to the end of reducing the number of school boards, which was in turn intended as a means of uncoupling education from property tax, which was intended as a means of asserting financial discipline (and other sorts of discipline) over local schools, which the government of the day considered a desirable end. Examples like that make the instrumentality of laws sound like a top‐down affair. Just as often it is bottom‐up. It is not only legislatures and courts but also individuals who use laws as means to their ends. Leona Helmsley wanted her dog to be adequately provided for after her own death.
    [Show full text]
  • Law and Morality: a Kantian Perspective
    Columbia Law School Scholarship Archive Faculty Scholarship Faculty Publications 1987 Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective George P. Fletcher Columbia Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation George P. Fletcher, Law and Morality: A Kantian Perspective, 87 COLUM. L. REV. 533 (1987). Available at: https://scholarship.law.columbia.edu/faculty_scholarship/1071 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at Scholarship Archive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarship Archive. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LAW AND MORALITY: A KANTIAN PERSPECTIVE George P. Fletcher* The relationship between law and morality has emerged as the cen- tral question in the jurisprudential reflection of our time. Those who call themselves positivists hold with H.L.A. Hart' that calling a statute or a judicial decision "law" need not carry any implications about the morality of that statute or decision.2 Valid laws might be immoral or unjust. Those who resist this reduction of law to valid enactments sometimes argue, with Lon Fuller, that moral acceptability is a neces- sary condition for holding that a statute is law; 3 or, with Ronald Dworkin, that moral principles supplement valid enactments as compo- 4 nents of the law. Whether the positivists or their "moralist" opponents are right about the nature of law, all seem to agree about the nature of morality. We have to distinguish, it is commonly said, between conventional and critical morality.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Foundations of East Asian Jurisprudence ― Confucianism, Legalism and Taoism ― 1)
    141 〈논 문〉 Ancient Foundations of East Asian Jurisprudence ― Confucianism, Legalism and Taoism ― 1) Chongko Choi* Foreword In the age of “Globalization,” the most important factor in the world politics seems to be the civilizations, not the ideologies, as Samuel Huntington eloquently asserts. With the magnificent emergence of the Chinese civilization on the world stage, many people, including intellectuals, pay attention with great interest to East Asian civilization.1) If you read books on Chinese philosophy, you may find that almost all the books overwhelmingly discuss ancient philosophies like Confucianism, Taoism, Legalism and “Hundred Schools”. This fact shows the richness of ancient philosophy and how it played continuously an important role in Chinese history. It applies not only to China, but also to Korea and Japan, perhaps to the whole of East Asia. I am currently trying to build up the concept of East Asian jurisprudence.2) * Professor of Law, Seoul National University 1) As the recent publications, Gina Barnes, China, Japan, Korea: The Rise of Civilization in East Asia, London, 1993: Warren Cohen, East Asia at the Center: Four Thousand Years of Engagement with the World, Columbia Univ. Press, 2000: Charles Holcombe, The Genesis of East Asia: 221BC-AD 907, Uni. of Hawaii Press, 2001. 2) Chongko Choi, Foundations of East Asian Jurisprudence, Seoul Law Journal, Vol. 41. No. 1, 2000, pp.60-76; Chongko Choi, The Development of East Asian Law till the End of 18th Century, Law in History, Vol. 1, 2000, pp.21-55; Chongko Choi, Foundations of Law and Justice in East Asia, Comparative Law, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Law, Positivism, and the Limits of Jurisprudence: a Modern Round
    Book Review Natural Law, Positivism, and the Limits of Jurisprudence: A Modern Round The Authority of Law: Essays in Law and Morality. By Joseph Raz. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979. Pp. ix, 292. Natural Law and Natural Rights. By John Finnis. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980. Pp. vii, 425. Ruth Gavisont In his recent collection of essays,' Joseph Raz presents and defends a version of positivism; in his first book-length contribution to legal philoso- phy,' John Finnis explores a natural law perspective. These two books, both published by Oxford, may thus serve as a reminder of the persistence of the debate between legal positivists and those adhering to the natural law tradition. As this review will show, the books demonstrate that these apparently contradictory schools of thought both can and must be inte- grated to enhance our understanding of the complex phenomenon of law. Rather than rival theories of law, positivism and natural law are, and should be taken to be, complementary and equally necessary approaches to a social institution of the utmost importance. The call to integrate these theories of law is anything but revolutionary. Sensitive legal scholars, even those who clearly identify themselves as ad- hering to one school or the other, have always granted that the two per- spectives are complementary rather than contradictory, and that the ap- peal of neither is transitory? Raz and Finnis, while presenting approaches t Senior Lecturer, Faculty of Law, Hebrew University, Jerusalem. An earlier version of this review was presented and discussed in December 1980 at a seminar of that Faculty of Law.
    [Show full text]
  • Shuman: Legal Positivism: Its Scope and Limitations
    Michigan Law Review Volume 62 Issue 1 1963 Shuman: Legal Positivism: Its Scope and Limitations Edgar Bodenheimer University of Utah Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, Law and Philosophy Commons, Law and Society Commons, and the Natural Law Commons Recommended Citation Edgar Bodenheimer, Shuman: Legal Positivism: Its Scope and Limitations, 62 MICH. L. REV. 154 (1963). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol62/iss1/12 This Book Reviews is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RECENT BOOKS LEGAL POSITIVISM: ITS SCOPE AND LIMITATIONS. By Samuel I. Shuman. Detroit: Wayne State University Press. 1963. Pp. vi, 265. $8.50. One of the criteria that might be applied in the evaluation of a book dealing with theoretical or philosophical matters in the social science field is whether the book raises and discusses questions that are meaningful and important in their relation to, and impact upon, human social life. Judged by this criterion, Professor Shuman's book will easily pass muster before a board of critics. Anyone interested in the law as a means of social control will concede that the problems taken up by Professor Shuman, notwithstanding their theoretical and philosophical character, have a decisive bearing upon the solution of issues that every organized society has to cope with.
    [Show full text]
  • Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivism
    Indiana Law Journal Volume 55 Issue 2 Article 1 Winter 1979 Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivism Genaro R. Carrio Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Legal History Commons Recommended Citation Carrio, Genaro R. (1979) "Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivism," Indiana Law Journal: Vol. 55 : Iss. 2 , Article 1. Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol55/iss2/1 This Lecture is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana Law Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Vol. 55, No. 2 INDIANA1979-1980 LAW JOURNAL Professor Dworkin's Views on Legal Positivismt GENARO R. CARRI6 * The expression "legal positivism" is intolerably ambiguous. It has been used in the past and is still used to designate a heterogeneous variety of attitudes, theses, conceptions and doctrines, all of which concern in different ways the social phenomenon known as "law." Some of them are incompatible with each other. Others are inter- connected by family ties. That is why in most cases it will not do to try to identify the general trend of ideas of a given jurist by saying that he is a positivist. Furthermore, when someone directs his at- tacks, indiscriminately, against "legal positivism," it may be quite confusing if he fails to state in what sense he is using that expres- sion.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered
    Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law Volume 9 Issue 1 Article 9 1977 Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered Neal Koch Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/jil Part of the International Law Commons Recommended Citation Neal Koch, Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered, 9 Case W. Res. J. Int'l L. 161 (1977) Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.case.edu/jil/vol9/iss1/9 This Comment is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Journals at Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law by an authorized administrator of Case Western Reserve University School of Law Scholarly Commons. 1977] COMMENT Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg Considered* N THE ARTICLE, Classical Legal Positivism at Nuremberg,' Stanley L. Paulson effectively demonstrates that the rejection of the criminal defenses offered at the Nuremberg Trials follows from the rejection of underlying classical legal positivist doctrines. Specifically, his aim is to show that noncontingent links exist be- tween the doctrines of classical legal positivism and the defenses of the act of state doctrine and superior orders. Paulson argues that the defenses of act of state and superior orders both presuppose the doctrine of absolute sovereignty. The presupposition underlying the act of state defense is explained in terms of Austin's analysis of positive legal rights as triadic rela- tions. The presupposition underlying the defense of superior or- ders is explained by analyzing the requirement of unconditional obedience. The Austinian theory of classical legal positivism depends upon the command doctrine and the doctrine of absolute sovereignty.
    [Show full text]